Skip to main content
Log in

Defining vision: what homology thinking contributes

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The specialization of visual function within biological function is reason for introducing “homology thinking” into explanations of the visual system. It is argued that such specialization arises when organisms evolve by differentiation from their predecessors. Thus, it is essentially historical, and visual function should be regarded as a lineage property. The colour vision of birds and mammals do not function the same way as one another, on this account, because each is an adaptation to special needs of the visual functions of predecessors—very different kinds of predecessors in each case. Thus, history underlies function. We also see how homology thinking figures in the hierarchical classification of visual systems, and how it supports the explanation of visual function by functional role analysis.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I am being deliberately vague when I speak of “things” being grouped together by common ancestry. These “things” can be traits, bone structures, behaviours, etc. See Matthen (2000) for a historical account, and Brigandt (this issue), Griffiths (this issue) and Love (this issue) for original discussion.

  2. I take “evolved from” to be an incompletely explicated historical notion that awaits further analysis. See, however, Brigandt (this issue) on ‘evolvability’ and Griffiths (this issue) for the importance of genetic and developmental processes in operational definitions of homology. I will rest content with treating homology as something of a black box, since my interest is in an application of homology thinking, not its explication. I do not speak, for example, about serial homology, though I assume that the definition given can be fleshed out in such a way as to include it.

  3. Karen Neander (2002) rightly insists that any adequate taxonomy should be able to accommodate variation and loss of functionality—organs of different size, genetically defective and diseased organs, and so on. She argues that only definitions in terms of teleological functions can accommodate such variation adequately (since something can possess a function but not perform it). She is wrong about this: the historically based definition of homology-class accommodates variation, but does not mention teleological functions. In fact, Neander herself implicitly appeals to historical origins. for it is only by identifying relations of evolutionary descent that naturalized teleology gets a grip on variation. Thus, I would claim that notions such as that of a “reproductively established family” (cf. Millikan 1984) implicitly appeal to homology-classes (see Griffiths, this issue). Neander and other proponents of historical approaches to “proper function” are in the same boat.

  4. I am very much in debt to Ingo Brigandt and Paul Griffiths for helping me get straight on this matter.

References

  • Amundson R, Lauder G (1994) Function without purpose: the uses of causal role function in evolutionary biology. Biol Philos 9:443–469

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Avian Brain Nomenclature Consortium (2005) Avian brains and a new understanding of vertebrate brain evolution. Nat Rev Neurosci 3:151–159

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach-y-Rita P, Tyler ME, Kaczmarek KA (2003) Seeing with the brain. Int J Human-Comput Interact 15:285–295

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins R (1983) The nature of psychological explanation. Bradford Books, MIT Press, Cambridge MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin C (1965) The expression of emotion in man and animals. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Delius JD, Emmerton J, Hörster W, Jäger R, Ostheim J (2000) Picture recognition in pigeons. In: Fagot J (eds) Picture perception in animals. Psychology Press, Hove England, pp 1–35

    Google Scholar 

  • Dominy NJ, Lucas PW (2001) Ecological importance of trichromatic vision in primates. Nature 410:363–366

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky M (2001) The poverty of the Linnaean hierarchy: a philosophical study of biological taxonomy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge England

    Google Scholar 

  • Gray RA (1991) Behaviour, brain and phylogeny: cladistic analyses of behavioural, morphological and molecular data. Int J Neurosci 57:296

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE (1994) Cladistic classification and functional explanation. Philos Sci 61:206–227

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE (1997) What emotions really are: the problem of psychological categories. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE (2006) Function, homology, and character individuation. Philos Sci 73:1–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE (2007) Evo-Devo meets the mind: towards a developmental evolutionary psychology. In: Sansom R, Brandon R (eds) Integrating evolution and development: from theory to practice. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 196–226

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC(1980) Adaptation. The Encyclopedia Einaudi. Eunaudi, Milan; Translated in Lewins R, Lewontin R (1985) The dialectical biologist. Cambridge MA, Harvard UP

  • Lewontin RC (1982) Organism & environment. In: Plotkin H (ed) Learning, development, culture. John Wiley, New York, pp 151–170

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC (1983) Gene, organism & environment. In: Bendall DS (ed) Evolution: from molecules to man. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 273–285

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthen M (1998) Biological universals and the nature of fear. J Philos 95:105–132

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen M (2000) What is a hand? What is a mind? Revue Internationale de Philosophie 214:653–672

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthen M (2005) Seeing, doing, and knowing: a philosophical theory of sense perception. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Medina L, Reiner A (2000) Do birds possess homologues of mammalian primary visual, somatosensory and motor cortices? Trend Neurosci 23:1–12

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan RG (1984) Language, thought, and other biological categories. Bradford Books, MIT Press, Cambridge MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Mollon JD (2000) Cherries among the leaves: the evolutionary origins of color vision. In: Davis S (ed) Color perception: philosophical, psychological, artistic, and computational perspectives. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 10–30

    Google Scholar 

  • Neander K (1991) Functions as selected effects: the conceptual analyst’s defence. Philos Sci 58:168–184

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander K (2002) Types of Traits: the importance of functional homologues. In: Ariew A, Cummins R, Perlman M (eds) Functions: new essays in the philosophy of psychology and biology. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 390–415

    Google Scholar 

  • Preuss T (2004) What is it like to be a human? In: Gazzaniga M (ed) Cognitive neurosciences, 3rd edn. Bradford Books, MIT Press, Cambridge MA, pp 5–22

    Google Scholar 

  • Regan BC, Julliot C, Simmen B, Viénot F, Charles-Dominique P, Mollon JD (2001) Fruits, foliage and the evolution of colour vision. Philos Trans Roy Soc Lond B 356:229–283

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1988) Reconstructing the past: parsimony, evolution, and inference. Bradford Books, MIT Press, Cambridge MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Surridge AK, Osorio D, Mundy NI (2003) Evolution and selection of trichromatic vision in primates. Trend Ecol Evol 18:198–205

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tjønneland A, Økland S, Nyland A (1987) Evolutionary aspects of the arthropod heart. Zool Scripta 16:167–175

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Many thanks to my fellow symposiasts for incisive discussion and many new ideas: Ingo Brigandt, Marc Ereshefsky, Paul Griffiths, and Alan Love. Special thanks to Paul and Ingo for written comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mohan Matthen.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Matthen, M. Defining vision: what homology thinking contributes. Biol Philos 22, 675–689 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-007-9088-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-007-9088-4

Keywords

Navigation