Skip to main content
Log in

Crossing the Associative/Inferential Divide: Ad hoc Concepts and the Inferential Power of Schemata

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

How do we construct ad hoc concepts, especially those characterised by emergent properties? A reasonable hypothesis, suggested both in psychology and in pragmatics (Relevance Theory), is that some sort of inferential processing must be involved. I argue that this inferential processing can be accounted for in associative terms. My argument is based on the notion of inference as associative pattern completion based on schemata, with schemata being conceived in turn as patterns of concepts and their relationships. The possible role of conscious attention in inferential processes of this sort is also addressed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It might also be argued that an associative account of inferences is not compatible with RT’s modularism. This point, however, is beyond the scope of this paper.

  2. “Everything about the production of inferences via pattern completion has a statistical character” (Barsalou 2005: 629).

  3. One of the referees has argued that, since I am concerned with a descriptive enterprise, questions of justification had better be left aside. His/her suspicion is that “justifies” here is ultimately just a placeholder for “causes”. To be sure, I am not concerned here with normative epistemological issues. However, there is a cognitive reason for speaking of justification and not of cause: while associations in a restrictive sense can only be causes of concept activation, schematic associations in my sense can be thought to justify concept activation, to the extent that they can act as premises in rules of inference having certain concepts as their conclusions. I have described these rules of inference in terms of generalised modus ponens. (Thus, to be precise, it is the use of schemata in these rules of inference, not schemata in themselves, that justifies the conclusion.) If this is a special, cognitive use of “justification”, so be it.

    The referee has two further objections to these considerations. One is that only sentential entities can act as inferential premises and conclusions. However, section 4 is precisely devoted to explaining why my generalised notion of modus ponens is thought to apply to non-sentential entities as well. The general idea is that sensorimotor representations have structure and can be combined productively in a way that is largely isomorphic to linguistic productivity. This is sufficient for sensorimotor representations to be subject to normative considerations, although this is not my concern here. The other objection is that my non-normative use of “justified” is scarcely clear. Does it mean “seems justified”? “This seems implausible—the referee says—since it would presuppose conscious awareness of the transition”. I agree that conscious awareness cannot be a general requirement for the kind of associative processes described here. As a matter of fact, in section 5 I propose that conscious awareness adds stability to the processes at issue, but the inferential structure is already provided by the schematic organization of associative knowledge. I insist that there is a clear distinction between the claim that associations are mere representations of co-occurrences and the claim that associations have schematic organization: in the latter case, but not in the former, activations can provide motivated transitions, that is, transitions from one content (p) to another (q) by means of a schema (if p then q), even when these transitions are not accompanied by conscious awareness.

  4. Incidentally, that notation may be used for co-indexing of arguments (as Recanati 2004 has shown), but for our purposes we can leave this issue aside.

  5. At least if we suppose that the metaphor is fresh and BULLDOZER* is not lexicalised. Otherwise, one should substitute an actual fresh metaphor for this example.

  6. It has even been suggested that attentional processing emerges itself “from the operations and interactions of very elementary processing units” (Shanks 2010: 275), that is, from basic associative mechanisms. However, for the present purposes we can leave this aside.

  7. In Barsalou’s account, ad hoc concepts are expressed by phrasal structures such as, for instance, “things to pack in a suitcase”. However, a concept combination such as PET BIRDS can be re-described in terms of the phrasal structure “birds which are also pets”.

References

  • Bargh, J.A. 1989. Conditional automaticity: Varieties of automatic influence on social perception and cognition. In Unintended thought, ed. J. Uleman and J. Bargh, 3–51. New York: Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bargh, J.A. 1990. Auto-motives: Preconscious determinants of social interaction. In Handbook of motivation and cognition, vol. 2, ed. E.T. Higgins and R.M. Sorrentino, 93–130. New York: Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou, L.W. 1983. Ad hoc categories. Memory and Cognition 11: 21–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou, L.W. 2005. Situated conceptualization. In Handbook of categorization in cognitive science, ed. H. Cohen and C. Lefebvre, 619–650. St. Louis: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou, L.W. 2010. Ad hoc categories. In The Cambridge Encyclopaedia of the Language Sciences, ed. P. Hogan, 86–87. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartlett, F.C. 1932. Remembering: An experimental and social study. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. 2007. How many pragmatic systems are there? In M.J, Frapolli (Ed.), Saying, Meaning, Referring. Essays on the Philosophy of François Recanati (pp. 1–17). New York: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. 2010. Metaphor: Ad hoc concepts, literal meaning and mental images. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 110(3): 295–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. 1952a. Function and Concept. In Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, ed. P. Geach and M. Black, 21–41. New York: Philosophical Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. 1952b. On Concept and Object. In Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, ed. P. Geach and M. Black, 42–56. New York: Philosophical Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hampton, J.A. 2006. Concepts as Prototypes. In The Psychology of Learning and Motivation: Advances in Research and Theory, vol. 46, ed. B.H. Ross, 79–113. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hampton, J.A., and M.L. Jönsson. 2012. Typicality and compositionality: The logic of combining vague concepts. In Oxford Handbook of Compositionality, ed. M. Werning, W. Hintzen, and E. Machery, 385–402. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hassin, R.R., H. Aarts, B. Eitam, R. Custers, and T. Kleiman. 2009. Non-conscious goal pursuit and the effortful control of behavior. In Oxford handbook of human action, ed. E. Morsella, J.A. Bargh, and P. Gollwitzer, 549–566. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huang, J.Y., Bargh, J.A. (in press). The Selfish Goal: Autonomously Operating Motivational Structures as the Proximate Cause of Human Judgment and Behavior. Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

  • Kintsch, Walter. 2000. Metaphor comprehension: a computational theory. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review 7: 257–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kintsch, Walter. 2001. Predication. Cognitive Science 25: 173–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mandler, G. 1979. Organization and repetition: Organization principles with special reference to rote learning. In Perspectives on memory research, ed. L. Nilsson, 293–327. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mazzone, M. 2011. Schemata and associative processes in pragmatics. Journal of Pragmatics 43: 2148–2159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mazzone, M. 2013. Attention to the speaker. The conscious assessment of utterance interpretations in working memory. Language and Communication 33: 106–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mazzone, M. 2014. The continuum problem: Modified Occam’s Razor and conventionalisation of meaning. International Review of Pragmatics 6: 29–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, E.K., and J.D. Cohen. 2001. An integrative theory of prefrontal cortex function. Annual Review of Neuroscience 24: 67–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, G.L. 2002. The Big Book of Concepts. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. 2004. Literal Meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. 2007. Reply to Carston. In Saying, Meaning, Referring. Essays on the Philosophy of François Recanati, ed. M.J. Frapolli, 49–54. New York: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubio-Fernandez, P. 2007. Suppression in metaphor interpretation: Differences between meaning selection and meaning construction. Journal of Semantics 24(4): 345–371.

  • Rumelhart, D.E., and A. Ortony. 1977. The representation of knowledge in memory. In Schooling and the acquisition of knowledge, ed. R.C. Anderson, R.J. Spiro, and W.E. Montague, 97–135. Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schank, R.C., and R. Abelson. 1977. Scripts, plans, goals and understanding. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shanks, D.R. 2010. Learning: From association to cognition. Annual Review of Psychology 61: 273–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, E.E. 1989. Concepts and induction. In Foundations of cognitive science, ed. M.I. Posner, 501–526. Cambridge, MA, US: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D., and D. Wilson. 2008. A deflationary account of metaphors. In The Cambridge Handbook of Metaphor and Thought, ed. R.W. Gibbs, 84–108. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Waltz, D.L., and J.B. Pollack. 1985. Massively Parallel Parsing: A Strongly Interactive Model of Natural Language Interpretation. Cognitive Science 9: 51–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, D., and R. Carston. 2006. Metaphor, relevance and the emergent property issue. Mind and Language 21(3): 404–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, D., and R. Carston. 2007. A unitary approach to lexical pragmatics: relevance, inference and ad hoc concepts. In Pragmatics, ed. N. Burton-Roberts, 230–260. New York: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood, J.N., D.D. Glynn, B.C. Phillips, and M.D. Hauser. 2007. The Perception of Rational, Goal-Directed Action in Nonhuman Primates. Science 317: 1402–5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marco Mazzone.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mazzone, M. Crossing the Associative/Inferential Divide: Ad hoc Concepts and the Inferential Power of Schemata. Rev.Phil.Psych. 5, 583–599 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-014-0201-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-014-0201-8

Keywords

Navigation