Skip to main content
Log in

God, the meaning of life, and a new argument for atheism

  • Article
  • Published:
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We raise various puzzles about the relationship between God (if God exists) and the meaning of life (if life has meaning). These difficulties suggest that, even if we assume that God exists, and even if (as we argue) God’s existence would entail that our lives have meaning, God is not and could not be the source of the meaning of life. We conclude by discussing implications of our arguments: (i) these claims can be used in a novel argument for atheism; (ii) these claims undermine an extant argument for God’s existence; and (iii) they suggest that atheism is consistent with our lives having meaning.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See (Metz 2013a) for a discussion of the meaning of life literature and these conventions (which Metz endorses).

  2. See Alcoff (Affolter 2007) for a defense of this view. See also Brown (1971), Levine (1987) and Cottingham (2003) for more on this view.

  3. And God-based approaches to the meaning of life have been endorsed by many non-philosophically oriented theists. The view has also been held by some philosophically oriented non-theists. Kahane (2013, p. 2) claims that “Russell thought that, in the absence of God, we must build our lives on ‘a foundation of unyielding despair.'” Albert Camus (1955) is arguably another example.

  4. To be precise, there are numerous possibilities: it might be that only some lives have meaning. Or perhaps all lives have meaning, though what gives life meaning might vary across individuals; i.e., why assume that there is only one meaning that life can have? Perhaps the meaning of one life is not the same as the meaning of another life? Or maybe a given life has meaning at some times but not others? Or perhaps the meaning that a given life has might change over time? To be clear, when we say that God could not be the source of the meaning of life, we mean that any time a particular life has meaning, whatever that meaning might be, God is not the reason.

  5. See, e.g., Wainwright (2012, Introduction), “The object of attitudes valorized in the major religious traditions is typically regarded as maximally great. Conceptions of maximal greatness differ but theists believe that a maximally great reality must be a maximally great person or God. Theists largely agree that a maximally great person would be omnipresent, omnipotent, omniscient, and all good. They do not agree on a number of God's other attributes, however”.

  6. While a large majority of philosophers of religion—whether they are theist, atheist, or agnostic—agree that the existence of God is inconsistent with the existence of gratuitous evil, it should at least be noted that there are some dissenters. For example, Peterson (2008), Hasker (1992), and van Inwagen (1995) argue that God and gratuitous evil are compossible. Kraay (2014) discusses some extant responses to van Inwagen’s view and offers a novel objection to it.

  7. Rowe has defended this argument in a number of papers. See, for example, Rowe (1979, 1984, 1986, 1988, 1991, 1996).

  8. There are several extant objections to skeptical theism. Ordinarily, theists say we are justified in trusting propositional information known only through divine revelation because God would not lie to us; yet, because skeptical theism leaves open the possibility that God might have morally obligatory reasons to lie to us, we are rendered unable to say how likely or unlikely God's lying would be (Wielenberg (2010); Hudson (2014)). There are further skeptical implications: Descartes ruled out the possibility that God would deceive us about the external world and the reliability of our senses, yet skeptical theism suggests that God could have a moral obligation, one beyond our comprehension, to globally deceive us (Wilks (2014)). Others have argued that skeptical theism destroys the possibility of moral deliberation (Piper 2007; Sehon 2010) or of inductive inference (Hasker 2010).

  9. Someone might object that if God exists, God exists necessarily. So there cannot be a possible world—like NG—in which God does not exist. But this objection conflates metaphysical and epistemological possibility. God’s existence or non-existence might be metaphysically necessary, but that is a separate issue from our knowledge of God’s existence, and so from epistemic possibility. Another way that we could have constructed the argument, which we do not pursue here, would be in terms of counterpossibles.

  10. A theist might object that even if our lives have intrinsic meaning, this does not imply that this meaning is independent of God. God creates us, so in a sense, this meaning that lives intrinsically have still depends upon God for its existence (in a causal sense). But we suggest that if lives can have meaning intrinsically, then these lives could have been caused by something aside from God (say, some purely naturalistic process) and still retain their meaning. In which case God is not necessary for life to have meaning.

  11. We would like to thank an anonymous referee for immensely helpful comments on an earlier draft.

References

  • Affolter, J. (2007). Human nature as God’s purpose. Religious Studies, 43, 443–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alston, W. (2002). What Euthyphro should have said. In W. L. Craig (Ed.), Philosophy of religion: A reader and guide (pp. 283–289). Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bond, E. J. (1983). Reason and value. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, D. (1971). Process philosophy and the question of life’s meaning. Religious Studies, 7, 13–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caldwell-Harris, C., Murphy, C. F., Velazquez, T., & McNamara, P. (2011). Religious belief systems of persons with high functioning autism. In Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society, Boston, MA.

  • Camus, A. (1955). The Myth of Sisyphus (J. O’Brian tr.). London: H. Hamilton.

  • Cottingham, J. (2003). On the meaning of life. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craig, W. (1994). The absurdity of life without God. Repr. In E. D. Klemke (Ed.), The meaning of life (2nd ed) (pp. 40–56) (2000). New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Craig, W. (1997). The Indispensability of theologicaly meta-ethical foundations for morality. Foundations, 5, 9–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crespi, B. J., & Badcock, C. (2008). Psychosis and autism as diametrical disorders of the social brain. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 31, 284–320.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gervais, W. (2013). Perceiving minds and Gods: How mind perception enables, constrains, and is triggered by belief in Gods. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8(4), 380–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, J. (1983). Is the existence of God relevant to the meaning of life? The Modern Schoolman, 60, 227–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (1978). The Panda’s peculiar thumb. Natural History, 87, 20–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haber, J. (1997). Contingency and the meaning of life. Philosophical Writings, 5, 32–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hasker, W. (1992). The necessity of gratuitous evil. Faith and Philosophy, 9, 23–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hasker, W. (2010). All too skeptical theism. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 68, 15–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hudson, H. (2014). The father of lies? In J. Kvanvig (Ed.), Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 147-166.

  • Kahane, G. (2013). Our cosmic insignificance. Nous, 4(48), 745–772.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kraay, K. (2014). Peter van Inwagen on gratuitous evil. Religious Studies, 50, 217–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leftow, B. (1990). Is God an abstract object? Nous, 24, 581–598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levine, M. (1987). What does death have to do with the meaning of life? Religious Studies, 23, 457–465.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maitzen, S. (2006). Divine hiddenness and the demographics of theism. Religious Studies, 42, 177–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metz, T. (2013a). Meaning in life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Metz, T. (2013b). The meaning of life. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.),The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2013 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/entries/life-meaning/.

  • Morriston, W. (2011). God and the ontological foundation of morality. Religious Studies, 48, 15–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical explanations. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peterson, M. (2008). C. S. Lewis on the necessity of gratuitous evil. In D. Baggett, G. Habermas, & J. Walls (eds.) C. S. Lewis as philosopher: Truth, goodness, and beauty. Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press.

  • Rowe, W. (1979). The problem of evil and some varieties of atheism. American Philosophical Quarterly, 16(4), 335–341.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowe, W. (1984). Evil and the theistic hypothesis: A response to S.J. Wykstra. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 16, 95–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowe, W. (1986). The empirical argument from evil. In Robert Audi & William Wainwright (Eds.), Rationality, religious belief and moral commitment. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowe, W. (1988). Evil and theodicy. Philosophical Topics, 16, 119–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowe, W. (1991). Ruminations about evil. Philosophical Perspectives, 5, 69–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowe, W. (1996). the evidential argument from evil: A second look. In D. Howard-Snyder (Ed.), The evidential argument from evil. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sehon, S. (2010). The problem of evil: Skeptical theism leads to moral paralysis. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 67, 67–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1993). Practical ethics (2nd ed.). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (2008). Evidence and evolution: The logic behind the science. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, P. (1995). The magnitude, duration, and distribution of evil. In God, knowledge, and mystery (pp. 96–122). Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

  • Wainwright, W. (2012). Concepts of God. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. (Spring 2013 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2013/entries/concepts-god/.

  • Wolf, S. (1997). Happiness and meaning: two aspects of the good life. Social Philosophy and Policy, 14, 207–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wykstra, S. (1984). The humean obstacle to evidential arguments from suffering: on avoiding the evils of ‘appearance’. International Journal for the Philosophy of Religion, 16(1984), 138–160.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jason Megill.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Megill, J., Linford, D. God, the meaning of life, and a new argument for atheism. Int J Philos Relig 79, 31–47 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-015-9538-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-015-9538-x

Keywords

Navigation