Skip to main content
Log in

Moral Responsibility and History Revisited

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Compatibilists about determinism and moral responsibility disagree with one another about the bearing of agents’ histories on whether or not they are morally responsible for some of their actions. Some stories about manipulated agents prompt such disagreements. In this article, I call attention to some of the main features of my own “history-sensitive” compatibilist proposal about moral responsibility, and I argue that arguments advanced by Michael McKenna and Manuel Vargas leave that proposal unscathed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Arpaly (2003), Dennett (2003), and Kapitan (2000) are discussed in Mele (2006, Chapter 7). Also see Mele (2008) on Cuypers (2006).

  2. Readers will notice that these stories assume the existence of morally responsible agents. This assumption begs no questions against my opponents in this article. Neither McKenna nor Vargas would reject it.

  3. As I understand valuing, “S at least thinly values X at a time if and only if at that time S both has a positive motivational attitude toward X and believes X to be good” (Mele 1995, p. 116). When values are understood as psychological states, I take them to have both of these dimensions by definition. This account of thinly valuing and the corresponding thin account of values are not intended as contributions to the theories of valuing and values; their purpose is to make my meaning clear.

  4. Some readers may worry that Beth has been replaced by “another person.” I lack the space to discuss worries about personal identity here, but see Mele (1995, p. 175, n. 22).

  5. For a critique of an instance of this use, see Mele (2006, pp. 150–153).

  6. I prefer writing in terms of positive and negative moral credit to writing in terms of moral credit and moral blame. Although I am willing to bow to tradition and use “blame,” deserved “praise” seems to suggest more than is entailed by being morally responsible for performing a good intentional action. Praise is a pretty lofty notion.

  7. McKenna focuses on another pair of stories of mine. I have focused here on the Chuck/Beth scenario because I take it to present “an intuitively more gripping challenge” to the view being criticized (Mele 1995, p. 156).

  8. McKenna offers some guidance on what the “very richest” properties include: being “richly self-controlled,” satisfying “something like Frankfurt’s hierarchical account of freely willed conduct,” and being “reasons-responsive” (2004, p. 180).

  9. An analysis of X identifies not only conceptually sufficient conditions for X but also the conceptually necessary conditions for X. Even if satisfying nonhistorical condition C is a sufficient condition for an agent’s being morally responsible for A-ing, it may be that some agents who do not satisfy C are morally responsible for A-ing and that some such agents must satisfy some historical condition in order to be morally responsible for A-ing.

  10. Imagine a bad-to-good transformation story that features Chuck’s being given a vivid vision of the Platonic Form of the Good for one day and his performing the good deeds described above. Would he be morally responsible for those deeds in this story? If someone were to explain the magic of The Good to me, I might be in a position to venture an answer. But notice that One Good Day is very different kind of story. Giving someone a vision of a Platonic Form is one thing; implanting values in him (after erasing his former values) is another.

  11. Vargas reports that a revisionist theory will attempt to vindicate “historicist intuitions” if they are “justifiable and/or metaphysically innocuous” (2006, p. 361).

  12. I am grateful to Michael McKenna, Manuel Vargas, and two anonymous referees for comments on a draft of this article. A draft of this article was written during my tenure of a 2007–2008 NEH Fellowship. (Any views, findings, conclusions, or recommendations expressed in this article do not necessarily reflect those of the National Endowment for the Humanities.)

References

  • Arpaly N (2003) Unprincipled virtue. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Cuypers S (2006) The trouble with externalist compatibilist autonomy. Philos Stud 129:171–196 doi:10.1007/s11098-004-7823-0

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson D (1987) Knowing one’s own mind. Proc Addresses Am Philos Assoc 60:441–458 doi:10.2307/3131782

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett D (2003) Freedom evolves. Viking, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer J, Ravizza M (1994) Responsibility and history. Midwest Stud Philos 19:430–451 doi:10.1111/j.1475-4975.1994.tb00297.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt H (1988) The importance of what we care about. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt H (2002) Reply to John Martin Fischer. In: Buss S, Overton L (eds) Contours of agency. MIT, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kane R (1985) Free will and values. State University of New York Press, Albany

    Google Scholar 

  • Kapitan T (2000) Autonomy and manipulated freedom. Philos Perspect 14:81–104

    Google Scholar 

  • McKenna M (2004) Responsibility and globally manipulated agents. Philos Top 32:169–192

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele A (1995) Autonomous agents: from self-control to autonomy. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele A (2006) Free will and luck. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mele A (2007) Moral responsibility and agents’ histories. Philos Studies doi:10.1007/s11098-007-9181-1

  • Mele A (2008) Manipulation, compatibilism, and moral responsibility. J Ethics (in press)

  • Vargas M (2006) On the importance of history for responsible agency. Philos Stud 127:351–382

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman D (1999) Born yesterday: personal autonomy for agents without a past. Midwest Stud Philos 23:236–266

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alfred R. Mele.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Mele, A.R. Moral Responsibility and History Revisited. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 12, 463–475 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-008-9131-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-008-9131-9

Keywords

Navigation