Skip to main content
Log in

The pessimistic induction: a bad argument gone too far

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I consider the pessimistic induction construed as a deductive argument (specifically, reductio ad absurdum) and as an inductive argument (specifically, inductive generalization). I argue that both formulations of the pessimistic induction are fallacious. I also consider another possible interpretation of the pessimistic induction, namely, as pointing to counterexamples to the scientific realist’s thesis that success is a reliable mark of (approximate) truth. I argue that this interpretation of the pessimistic induction fails, too. If this is correct, then the pessimistic induction is an utter failure that should be abandoned by scientific anti-realists.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Bird A. (2007a) What is scientific progress?. Noûs 41: 64–89

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird A. (2007b) Inference to the only explanation. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74: 424–432

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd R. (1989) What realism implies and what it does not. Dialectica 43: 5–29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caven R. M. (1921) The foundations of chemical theory: The elements of physical and general chemistry. D. van Nostrand Co, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt M. (2011) Are unconceived alternatives a problem for scientific realism. Journal for General Philosophy of Science 42: 285–293

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dopplet G. D. (2011) From standard scientific realism and structural realism to best current theory realism. Journal for General Philosophy of Science 42: 295–316

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P. (2011) Induction, samples, and kinds. In: Campbell J., O’Rourke M., Slater M. (eds) Carving nature at its joins: Topics in contemporary philosophy. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 33–52

    Google Scholar 

  • Held, C. (2011). Truth does not explain predictive success. Analysis. doi:10.1093/analysis/anr010.

  • Kitcher P. (1993) The advancement of science: Science without legend, objectivity without illusions. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Lange M. (2002) Baseball, pessimistic inductions and the turnover fallacy. Analysis 62: 281–285

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laudan L. (1981) A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science 48: 19–49

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis P. J. (2001) Why the pessimistic induction is a fallacy. Synthese 129: 371–380

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lipton P. (2000) Tracking track records. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. Supplementary Volumes 74: 179–205

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lipton P. (2005) The truth about science. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 360: 1259–1269

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magnus P. D., Callender C. (2004) Realist ennui and the base rate fallacy. Philosophy of Science 71: 320–338

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mizrahi, M. (2012). Why the ultimate argument for scientific realism ultimately fails. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 43, 132–138.

  • Muller F. A. (2008) In defence of constructive empiricism: Maxwell’s master argument and aberrant theories. Journal for General Philosophy of Science 39: 131–156

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nola R. (2008) The optimistic meta-induction and ontological continuity: The case of the electron. In: Soler L., Sankey H., Hoyningen-Huene P. (eds) Rethinking scientific change and theory comparison: Stabilities, ruptures, incommensurabilities?. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 159–202

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha S. (2001) What did hume really show about induction?. The Philosophical Quarterly 51: 307–327

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Park S. (2011) A confutation of the pessimistic induction. Journal for General Philosophy of Science 42: 75–84

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré H. (1952) Science and hypothesis. Dover, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos S. (1996) Scientific realism and the pessimistic induction. Philosophy of Science 63: S306–S314

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos S. (1999) Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos S. (2006) Thinking about the ultimate argument for realism. In: Cheyne C., Worrall J. (eds) Rationality & reality: Essays in honour of Alan Musgrave. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 133–156

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2007). The fine structure of inference to the best explanation. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LXXIV(2), 441–448.

  • Putnam H. (1975) Mathematics, matter, and method. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam H. (1978) Meaning and the moral sciences. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Saatsi J. T. (2005) On the pessimistic induction and two fallacies. Philosophy of Science 72: 1088–1098

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen B. C. (1980) The scientific image. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen B.C. (1989) Laws and symmetry. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wray, K. B. (2011). Success and truth in the realism/anti-realism debate. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-011-9931-7.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Moti Mizrahi.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Mizrahi, M. The pessimistic induction: a bad argument gone too far. Synthese 190, 3209–3226 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-012-0138-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-012-0138-3

Keywords

Navigation