Skip to main content
Log in

What makes biological organisation teleological?

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper argues that biological organisation can be legitimately conceived of as an intrinsically teleological causal regime. The core of the argument consists in establishing a connection between organisation and teleology through the concept of self-determination: biological organisation determines itself in the sense that the effects of its activity contribute to determine its own conditions of existence. We suggest that not any kind of circular regime realises self-determination, which should be specifically understood as self-constraint: in biological systems, in particular, self-constraint takes the form of closure, i.e. a network of mutually dependent constitutive constraints. We then explore the occurrence of intrinsic teleology in the biological domain and beyond. On the one hand, the organisational account might possibly concede that supra-organismal biological systems (as symbioses or ecosystems) could realise closure, and hence be teleological. On the other hand, the realisation of closure beyond the biological realm appears to be highly unlikely. In turn, the occurrence of simpler forms of self-determination remains a controversial issue, in particular with respect to the case of self-organising dissipative systems.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Bailly & Longo (2011, pp. 182–187). As an example of how these principles are used in physical and biological descriptions see also a textbook in dynamical systems theory, like Rosen (1970).

  2. It is the mainstream approach especially for biologists, but of course not the only one. See Perlman (2004) for a comprehensive review of the contemporary debate on teleology, which analyses the evolutionary approach in a wider context of teleological perspectives. The organisational approach, in our view, can provide a further option, and, we will argue, a naturalistic grounding of teleology that does not incur the limitations of the evolutionary and other approaches, such as the cybernetic one.

  3. For instance Ayala (1970), Millikan (1989), Neander (1991), Kitcher (1993), Ruse (2000).

  4. We are aware of the fact that it is quite unusual to claim that lineages have goals. Yet, we maintain that the appeal to the evolutionary loop between effects and existence to explain teleology implies that the system in which such a loop is realised is the lineage. This claim would deserve a more detailed examination, that we leave for a future work.

  5. The evolutionary framework is also at the basis of the mainstream approach in the philosophical debate about biological functions, i.e. the so-called selected effect theory (Millikan 1989; Godfrey-Smith 1994). By interpreting Wright’s etiological account (Wright 1973) in evolutionary terms, the evolutionary framework defines functions as adaptations.

  6. See for example Zammito (2006) and Sloan (2012).

  7. Claude Bernard’s work is neither the only nor the first contribution to a scientific grounding of teleological properties of living systems in the nineteenth century, especially if we take into consideration German Biology (see Lenoir 1981, 1982, for more details). Yet, Bernard’s work is crucial for the purposes of this paper inasmuch as it played an important role in the early development of the idea of biological self-determination by influencing the traditions of research of French Molecular Biology, Cybernetics, and that branch of Systems Theory which gave rise to the idea of biological autonomy.

  8. For the historical relationship between Cybernetics and French molecular biology, see Fox Keller (2002).

  9. We can find here a convergence of genetics, Bernard’s theory and cybernetic modelling. The genome evolves in such a way as to provide not only the mechanisms for the construction of structure, but also cybernetic mechanisms for the conservation and stabilisation of the internal milieu of individual living systems (see for example Morange 1994, p. 163). In such a way, the teleological dimensions of adaptation and adaptivity are integrated in a unique framework.

  10. For an analysis of the contributions of Weiss Piaget, Rosen, and the autopoietic theory to the organisational approach in biology, see Damiano (2012) and Bich and Arnellos (2013).

  11. In the following section, we will discuss in some details the conceptual relations between biological organisation and physical self-organisation.

  12. As we will discuss in the Sect. 3, it is important not to confuse the water cycle, to which we are referring here (the hydrologic system alone), with supra-organismal systems such as ecosystems, or with even more comprehensive climatic systems which possibly include biological organisms as components.

  13. Rosen uses and re-interprets Aristotelian causes as a way of answering the question “why x?” in a description of a natural system, where x is a component or feature of such a system. Rosen does so in terms of physical, chemical and biological descriptions, by interpreting Aristotelian causes in strict relation to mathematical formalism and associating them with physical structures or quantities. In the case of the dynamical description of physical systems, he associates the initial state of a system with the material cause, the parameters with formal cause and the operators with efficient cause (Rosen 1985b). According to Rosen, in the dynamical descriptions of physics there is no space for final causes. When he applies the Aristotelian account in a relational description of biological systems, such as the one he develops for (M,R)-Systems (Rosen 1972, 1991), he identifies: the material cause with matter and energy flowing in the system (the input and the output of a process); the efficient cause with a material structure that affects the process without being directly affected in turn, which he expresses mathematically as a mapping that transforms the input into the output; the formal cause with the global topology of the network, that is, in mathematical terms, the whole graph built on the category formalism. As we discuss below, he characterises final causation with the inverse of efficient causation.

  14. It could also be a membrane channelling the passage of molecules inside a cell, the heart pumping blood, etc.

  15. Rosen relies on category theory in order to formally describe efficient causes as mappings. Indeed, category theory allows expressing the activity of components as mappings and, at the same time, mappings themselves as the products of other mappings. This adequately captures the hierarchical and manifold character of efficient causes in living systems: they act on processes (enzymes catalyse reactions) and, at the same time, they are produced by other efficient causes (enzymes are produced by other metabolic processes within the cell).

  16. Let us consider the previous example of the catalyst as an instance of efficient cause. A minimal case of closure to efficient causation would be a system which produces all the catalysts necessary for its own activity (Cornish-Bowden 2006). This is what is usually called “catalytic closure” (Kauffman 2000).

  17. Their local conservation makes the conceptual difference with respect to material causes. For instance, while the substrates of a chemical reactions are converted into the products, the catalysts accelerate the reactions without being consumed by it. Because of their conservation, cataysts are constraints, while substrates are material causes. See Mossio et al. (2013) for an account of constraints and their role in organisational closure.

  18. Biological self-determination should be carefully distinguished from self-organisation. As mentioned, ‘self-organisation’ refers nowadays to physical spontaneous phenomena. In contrast, biological systems are (mostly) not spontaneous, in spite of the fact that they generate their own components. Accordingly, to avoid ambiguities, we submit that closure entails a form of self-maintenance of the whole, and not its self-generation or self-organisation.

  19. These two levels of causation are of course not the only ones which coexist in biological systems. These usually realise many levels of organisation (unicellular, multicellular...), and possess also regulatory capacities. The point here is that biological organisation as a form of self-constraint requires, necessarily, a distinction between these two specific regimes.

  20. Or, at least, in systems being “at the edge” of the biological domain as, possibly, complex chemical networks. In this paper, we do not discuss these categories of systems to the extent that this does not interfere with our main argument.

  21. We cannot exclude a-priori that there might be cases of physicochemical (proto-biological) systems realising closure and, therefore, a basic form of intrinsic teleology. However, it should be underscored that this issue does not concern exclusively the organisational account. According to Bedau (1991), for instance, some kinds of crystals might undergo a process of natural selection, insofar as they are capable, in some adequate circumstances, of reproduction, variation and heredity. Accordingly, they would be teleological from an evolutionary perspective. As such, hence, the fact that the organisational account might possibly ascribe teleology to some physical systems does not constitute a principled difference (or weakness) with respect to the evolutionary one.

  22. Therefore, we deal here with physicochemical regimes which would not be “supra-organismal”, as the already mentioned ecosystems or (possibly) larger climate systems.

  23. “A candle flame [...] makes several active contributions to its own persistence. It maintains above combustion threshold temperature. It vaporises wax into a continuing supply of fuel. In a standard atmosphere and gravitational field, it induces convection, which pulls in continuing oxygen and removes combustion products. A candle flame, in other words, tends to maintain itself; it exhibits self-maintenance” (Bickhard 2000, http://www.lehigh.edu/~mhb0/autfuncrep.html.

  24. A similar thesis has been proposed by Bishop (2008) in terms of direct self-constraint interpreted as a form of downward causation.

References

  • Anderson, P. W. (1985). Broken symmetry, emergent properties, dissipative structures, life: Are they related? In F. E. Yakes (Ed.), Self-organizing systems: The emergence of order (pp. 445–458). New York: Plenum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arnellos, A., & Moreno, A. (2012). How functional differentiation originated in prebiotic evolution. Ludus Vitalis, XX, 37, 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashby, R. (1956). An introduction to cybernetics. London: Chapman & Hall.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Atkins, P. W. (1984). The second law. New York: Scientific American.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ayala, F. J. (1970). Teleological explanations in evolutionary biology. Philosophy of Science, 30(1), 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bailly, F., & Longo, G. (2011). Mathematics and the natural sciences. The physical singularity of life. London: Imperial College Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barandiaran, X., & Moreno, A. (2008). Adaptivity: From metabolism to behavior. Adaptive Behavior, 16, 325–344.

  • Bechtel, W. (2007). Biological mechanisms: Organized to maintain autonomy. In F. Boogerd, F. Bruggerman, J. H. Hofmeyr, & H. V. Westerhoff (Eds.), Systems biology: Philosophical foundations (pp. 269–302). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bedau, M. (1991). Can biological teleology be naturalized? The Journal of Philosophy, 88(11), 647–655.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bedau, M. (1992). Goal-directed systems and the good. The Monist, 75(1), 34–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernard, C. (1865). Introduction à l’étude de la médecine expérimentale. Paris: Baillière.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernard, C. (1878). Leçons sur les phénomènes de la vie communs aux animaux et aux végétaux. Paris: Baillière.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bich, L. (2012a). L’ordine invisibile. Organizzazione, autonomia e complessità del vivente. Soveria Mannelli: Robbettino Università.

  • Bich, L. (2012b). Complex emergence and the living organization. An epistemological framework for biology. Synthese, 185(2), 215–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bich, L., & Arnellos, A. (2013). Autopoiesis, autonomy and organizational biology: Critical remarks on “Life After Ashby”. Cybernetics and Human Knowing, 19(4), 75–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard, M. H. (2000). Autonomy, function, and representation. Communication and Cognition—Artificial Intelligence, 17(3–4), 111–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, R. (2008). Downward causation in fluid convection. Synthese, 160(2), 229–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cannon, W. B. (1929). Organization for physiological homeostasis. Physiological Reviews, 9(3), 399–431.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, W., & Bickhard, M. (2002). The process dynamics of normative function. The Monist, 85(1), 3–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, W. D., & Hooker, C. A. (2000). Autonomy and the emergence of intelligence: Organised interactive construction. Communication and Cognition—Artificial Intelligence, 17(3–4), 133–157.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cornish-Bowden, A. (2006). Putting the systems back into systems biology. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 49, 475–489.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crutchfield, J. P. (1994). The calculi of emergence: Computations. Dynamics, and Induction, Physica D, 75, 11–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damiano, L. (2012). Co-emergences in life and science: A double proposal for biological emergentism. Synthese, 185(2), 273–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1859). On the origin of species. London: John Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox Keller, E. (2000). The century of the gene. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox Keller, E. (2002). Making sense of life. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (1994). A modern history theory of functions. Nous, 28, 344–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, T. S. (1968). Ideas of life and matter (Vol. 2). Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huneman, P. (Ed.). (2007). Understanding purpose?: Kant and the philosophy of biology. Rochester, NY: University of Rochester Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, F. (1970). La logique du vivant. Une historie de l’hérédité. Paris: Gallimard (Eng. Trans. by B. E. Spillmann, The Logic of Life, New York: Pantheon Books, 1973).

  • Jacob, F., & Monod, J. (1961). Genetic regulatory mechanisms in the synthesis of proteins. Journal of Molecular Biology, 3, 318–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. (1953). A critique of cybernetics. Social Research, 20, 172–192.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. (1966). The Phenomenon of Life. Towards a Philosophical Biology. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Juarrero, A. (1999). Dynamics in Action. Intentional Behaviour as a Complex System. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1781/1998). Critique of pure reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kant, I. (1790/1987). Critique of Judgment. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

  • Kauffman, S. (2000). Investigations. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1993). Function and Design. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 18(1), 379–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lenoir, T. (1981). Teleology without regrets. The transformation of physiology in Germany 1790–1847. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 12, 293–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lenoir, T. (1982). The strategy of life. Teleology and mechanics in nineteenth century german biology. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, R. C. (1991). Biology as Ideology. The Doctrine of DNA. Concord: House of Anansi Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, R. C. (2000). The triple helix. Gene, organism, environment. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longo, G., & Tendero, P. E. (2008). L’alphabet, la machine et l’ADN: l’incomplétude causale dela théorie de la programmacion en biologie moléculaire. In P. A. Miquel (Ed.), Biologie du XXIe Siècle:Évolution des Concepts Fondateurs (pp. 185–218). Paris: DeBoeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H. & Varela, F. J. (1973), De Máquinas y Seres Vivos: Una teoría sobre la organización biológica, Santiago: Editorial Universitaria. In H. Maturana, & F. J. Varela (Eds.), 1980, Autopoiesis and Cognition. The Realization of the Living. Dordrecht: North Holland.

  • Mayr, E. (1961). Cause and effect in biology. Science, 134, 1501–1506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1974). Teleological and teleonomic, a new analysis. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 14, 91–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (1989). In defense of proper functions. Philosophy of Science, 56, 288–302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Minati, G., & Pessa, E. (2006). Collective beings. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Monod, J. (1970). Les hasard et la necessité. Paris: Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morange, M. (1994). Histoire de la biologie moléculaire. Paris: Editions La Découverte (Eng. Trans. by M. Cobb, A History of Molecular Biology, Cambridge MA. Harvard University Press, 1998).

  • Moreno, A., & Ruiz-Mirazo, K. (1999). Metabolism and the problem of its universalization. BioSystems, 49(1), 45–61.

  • Moreno, A., & Ruiz-Mirazo, K. (2009). The problem of the emergence of functional diversity in prebiotic evolution. Biology and Philosophy, 24(5), 585–605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moreno, A., & Mossio, M. (in press). Biological autonomy: A philosophical and theoretical enquiry. Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Moreno, A., Etxeberria, A., & Umerez, J. (2008). The autonomy of biological individuals and artificial models. Biosystems, 91(2), 309–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mossio, M., Bich, L., & Moreno, A. (2013). Emergence, closure and inter-level causation in biological systems. Erkenntnis, 78(2), 153–178.

  • Mossio, M., Saborido, C., & Moreno, A. (2009). An organizational account of biological functions. British Journal of Philosophy of Science, 60(4), 813–841.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (1991). Functions as selected effects: The conceptual analyst’s defence. Philosophy of Science, 58, 168–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nicolis, G., & Prigogine, I. (1977). Self-organization in nonequilibrium systems: From dissipative structures to order through fluctuations. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nunes-Neto, N., Moreno, A., & El Hani, C. N. (2014). Function in ecology: An organizational approach. Biology and Philosophy, 29(1), 123–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pattee, H. H. (1973). The physical basis and origin of hierarchical control. In H. H. Pattee (Ed.), Hierarchy theory (pp. 71–108). New York: Braziller.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perlman, M. (2004). The modern philosophical resurrection of teleology. The Monist, 87(1), 3–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1967). Biologie et connaissance. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prigogine, I., & Stengers, I. (1988). Entre le temps et l’éternité. Paris: Libraire Arthème Fayard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, R. (1970). Dynamical system theory in biology. Stability theory and its applications. New York: Wiley-Interscience.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, R. (1972). Some relational cell models: The metabolism-repair systems. In R. Rosen (Ed.), Foundations of mathematical biology (Vol. II, pp. 217–253). New York: Academic Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, R. (1985a). Organisms as causal systems which are not mechanisms: An essay into the nature of complexity. In R. Rosen (Ed.), Theoretical biology and complexity. Three essays on the natural philosophy of complex systems. Orlando: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, R. (1985b). Anticipatory systems. Oxford: Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, R. (1991). ife itself. A comprehensive inquiry into the nature, origin, and fabrication of life. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenblueth, A., Wiener, N., & Bigelow, J. (1943). Behaviour, purpose and teleology. Philosophy of Science, 10(1), 18–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruiz-Mirazo, K. (2001). Physical conditions for the appearance of autonomous systems with open-ended evolutionary capacities. PhD Dissertation, University of the Basque Country.

  • Ruse, M. (2000). Teleology: Yesterday, today, and tomorrow? Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 31(1), 213–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saborido, C., Mossio, M., & Moreno, A. (2011). Biological organization and cross-generation functions. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62, 583–606.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sloan, P. (2012). How was teleology eliminated in early molecular biology? Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 43(1), 140–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sommerhoff, G. (1950). Analytical biology. London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toepfer, G. (2012). Teleology and its constitutive role for biology as the science of organized systems in nature. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 43(1), 113–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Umerez, J. (1994). Jerarquias Autónomas - Un estudio sobre el origen y la naturaleza de loas procesos de control y de formacion de niveles en eistemas naturales complejos. Ph.D. Dissertation, University of the Basque Country.

  • Varela, F., & Maturana, H. (1972). Mechanism and biological explanation. Philosophy of Science, 39(3), 378–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Bertalanffy L. (1949). Das Biologische Weltbild: Die Stellung des Lebens in Natur und Wissenshaft. Bern: Francke (eng. ed., 1952, Problems of Life: An Evaluation of Modern Biological Thought. London: Watts & Co).

  • Weber, A., & Varela, F. J. (2002). Life after Kant: Natural purposes and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1(2), 97–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waddington, C. H. (1962). The nature of life. New York: Atheneum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waddington, C. H. (1968). The basic ideas of biology. In C. H. Waddington (Ed.), Towards a theoretical biology (Vol. 1, pp. 1–41)., Prolegomena New York: Atheneum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiss, P. (1968). Dynamics of development. Experiments and inferences. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiener, N. (1948). Cybernetics: Or control and communication in the animal and in the machine. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.

  • Wright, L. (1973). Functions. Philosophical Review, 82, 139–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zammito, J. (2006). Teleology then and now: the question of Kant’s relevance for contemporary controversies over function in biology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 37(4), 748–770.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This work was funded by Ministerio de Ciencia y Innovación, Spain (‘Juan de la Cierva’ program to LB); Research Project of the Spanish Government (FFI2011-25665 to LB) and by the Basque Government (IT 590-13, postdoctoral fellowship to LB).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Matteo Mossio.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mossio, M., Bich, L. What makes biological organisation teleological?. Synthese 194, 1089–1114 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0594-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0594-z

Keywords

Navigation