Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Abstract

The aim of this paper is to provide a preliminary defence of the use of the concept of dignity in legal and ethical discourse. This will involve the application of three philosophical insights: (1) Ludwig Wittgenstein’s notion of language-games; (2) his related approach to understanding the meanings of words (sometimes summarised as ‘meaning is use’); and (3) Jeremy Waldron’s layered understanding of property wherein ‘property’ consists in an abstract concept fleshed out in numerous particular conceptions. These three insights will be applied, in the first place, to the concept of ‘dignity’, which is chosen here as a good example of a concept which is both vague and contested in legal and ethical discourse, but which can nevertheless be rendered workable by the application of the aforementioned insights. Later, the analysis will be extended briefly to some other troublesome concepts in order to demonstrate its general application. This paper is concerned primarily with formal, rather than substantive questions about dignity. Matters of content will be touched on only insofar as is necessary to illustrate and illuminate my argument about how we ought to approach (rather than answer) questions about dignity. It should be emphasised that because there is no intention of exploring substantive questions in any depth, the discussion here will not delve into the criticisms of ‘speciesism’ often levelled against the idea of ‘human dignity’. ‘Speciesist’ theories are those that claim that the status, value, or rights of human beings can be regarded as being higher than that of other animals, purely on the basis of their membership of the human species, and without justifying the distinction by pointing to any relevant capacity or characteristic possessed by all and only human beings. For a critical description of speciesism see, e.g., Singer [18] Chapter Three passim; for present purposes, the term ‘dignity’ will be used synonymously with ‘human dignity’, and concerns about speciesism will not be considered.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The term ‘healthcare law and ethics’ in this context is used to signify the kind of legal discourse with a significant bioethical content that is variously called ‘medical law and ethics’, ‘bioethics and biolaw’ and so on.

  2. The preamble to the UDHR states that ‘recognition of the inherent dignity and of the equal and inalienable rights of all members of the human family is the foundation of freedom, justice and peace in the world’, and Article 1declares that ‘[a]ll human beings are born free and equal in dignity and rights.’

  3. For example, the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights; the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights; the Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Racial Discrimination; the Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against Women; and the Convention on the Rights of the Child. (With thanks to my colleague, Elaine Webster, for these examples.)

  4. Pretty v United Kingdom (2002) 35 EHRR 1.

  5. Evans v United Kingdom (2006) 43 EHRR 21; see also the Grand Chamber judgment: Evans v United Kingdom 6339/05 [2007] ECHR 265 (10 April 2007).

  6. Gallie [7].

  7. Citing P v S and Cornwall CC (C-13/94) [1996] E.C.R. I-2143 EC and KB v NHS Pensions Agency (C-117/01) [2004] E.C.R. I-541 ECJ.

  8. For example, Ruth Macklin has complained that ‘to invoke the concept of dignity without clarifying its meaning is to use a mere slogan’ ([11] 1420).

  9. [2008] UKHL 25.

  10. Ibid. at paragraph 53 per Lord Rodger of Earlsferry.

  11. Ibid. at paragraph 3 per Lord Bingham of Cornhill.

  12. Ibid. at paragraph 17 per Lord Scott of Foscote.

  13. Ibid.

  14. Ibid. at paragraph 18.

  15. Ibid. at paragraph 87, per Lord Neuberger of Abbotsbury.

References

  1. Bagaric, M., and J. Allen. 2006. The vacuous concept of dignity. Journal of Human Rights 5: 257–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Beyleveld, D., and R. Brownsword. 2001. Human dignity in bioethics and biolaw. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Dupré, C. 2009. Unlocking human dignity: Towards a theory for the 21st century. European Human Rights Law Review 2: 190–205.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Dworkin, R.M. 1979. Taking rights seriously (revised edition). London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Feldman, D. 1999. Human dignity as a legal value—Part 1. In: Public law 682–702.

  6. Fox-Decent, E. 2009. Indigenous peoples and human dignity. In: Dignity: A Special Focus on Vulnerable Groups, ed. Mégret, Hoffmann et al. Research paper for the swiss initiative to commemorate the 60th anniversary of the universal declaration of human rights, 34–46.

  7. Gallie, W.B. 1956. Essentially contested concepts, 56. In: Proceedings of the aristotelian society, 167.

  8. Gray, J. 1977. On the contestability of social and political concepts. In: 5 Political theory, 331.

  9. Gross, A, and Provost, R. 2009. Human dignity and sexual identity. In: Dignity: A Special Focus on Vulnerable Groups, ed. Mégret, Hoffmann et al. Research paper for the Swiss initiative to commemorate the 60th anniversary of the universal declaration of human rights, 70–77.

  10. Honoré, A.M. 1961. Ownership. In Oxford essays in jurisprudence, ed. A.G. Guest. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Macklin, R. 2003. Dignity is a useless concept. British Medical Journal 327: 1419–1420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. McCrudden, C. 2008. Human dignity and judicial interpretation of human rights. European Journal of International Law 19(4): 655–724.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Mégret, F., Hoffmann, F., et al. 2009. Dignity: A special focus on vulnerable groups. Research paper for the Swiss initiative to commemorate the 60th anniversary of the universal declaration of human rights.

  14. Mégret, F. 2009. The Elderly. In: Dignity: A Special Focus on Vulnerable Groups ed. Mégret, Hoffmann et al. Research paper for the Swiss initiative to commemorate the 60th anniversary of the universal declaration of human rights, 17–32.

  15. Naffine, N. 2003. Who are law’s persons? From cheshire cats to responsible subjects 66. Modern Law Review 346.

  16. Pinker, S. 2008. The stupidity of dignity. The New Republic. Accessed at http://www.tnr.com/article/the-stupidity-dignity.

  17. Rawls, J.A. 1971. Theory of justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Singer, P. 1993. Practical ethics, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Van Engeland, A., and Narain, V. 2009. Women in religious contexts. In: Dignity: A special focus on Vulnerable Groups, ed. Mégret, Hoffmann et al. Research paper for the Swiss initiative to commemorate the 60th anniversary of the universal declaration of human rights, 47–58.

  20. Waldron, J. 1988. The right to private property. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Waldron, J. 2007. Dignity and rank. European Journal of Sociology 48(2): 201–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Wittgenstein, L. 1976. Philosophical investigations, Oxford: Basil Blackwell (trans: Anscombe, G.E.M).

Download references

Acknowledgment

I am grateful to my colleague, Elaine Webster, for helpful discussion of dignity in the Human Rights law context.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mary Neal.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Neal, M. Dignity, Law and Language-Games. Int J Semiot Law 25, 107–122 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-011-9230-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-011-9230-0

Keywords

Navigation