Skip to main content
Log in

Moral Self-Knowledge in Kantian Ethics

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Kant’s duty of self-knowledge demands that one know one’s heart—the quality of one’s will in relation to duty. Self-knowledge requires that an agent subvert feelings which fuel self-aggrandizing narratives and increase self-conceit; she must adopt the standpoint of the rational agent constrained by the requirements of reason in order to gain information about her moral constitution. This is not I argue, contra Nancy Sherman, in order to assess the moral goodness of her conduct. Insofar as sound moral practice requires moral self-knowledge and moral self-knowledge requires a theoretical commitment to a conception of the moral self, sound moral agency is for Kant crucially tied to theory. Kant plausibly holds that self-knowledge is a protection against moral confusion and self-deception. I conclude that although his account relies too heavily on the awareness of moral law to explain its connection to moral development, it is insightful and important in Kantian ethics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For a decisive counter argument to Williams’s claim about the role of duty in Kantian moral psychology see Herman (1993).

  2. This raises the issue (which I will not here discuss) of how to reconcile Kant’s earlier a priori “pure” ethics with his later “impure”ethics or practical anthropology. For an extended discussion see Louden (2000).

  3. Cases of sense perceptions of which we are not aware, but whose existence we can infer, are cases of obscure ideas (this form of idea makes, for example, sexual repression possible). Kant notes: “we are often enough the victims of obscure ideas which are reluctant to vanish even when understanding has thrown light upon them. To arrange for his grave in his garden or under a shady tree, in a field or in a dry plot of ground, is often a very important affair to a dying man, even though he knows that if he chooses the one, he has no reason to hope for a nice view; and if he chooses the other, he has no reason to worry about catching a cold.” (2006, AK 7: 136–137).

  4. Moral fanatics base their reason for action on a pathological incentive and produce “a frivolous, high-flown, fantastic cast of mind, flattering themselves with a spontaneous goodness of heart that needs neither spur nor bridle and for which not even a command is necessary and thereby forgetting their obligation, which they ought to think of rather than merit.”

  5. Moran writes: “The rakehell as described seems to attempt a relation to his original shame, which does not involve viewing the world through it (in this case, himself and his actions), but instead treats it as an opaque psychological fact about himself that he has this attitude, a fact from which he can draw certain conclusions—conclusions which in this case conflict with the original attitude itself” p. 188.

References

  • Ameriks K (2000) Kant’s theory of mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Boyle M (2009) Two kinds of self-knowledge. Philos Phenomenol Res LXXVIII(1):133–164

    Google Scholar 

  • Herman B (1993) Integrity and impartiality. In her The practice of moral judgment. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, pp 23–44

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1965) Critique of pure reason (trans: Norman Kemp Smith). St. Martin, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1991) The metaphysics of morals (trans: Mary Gregor). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1997a) Critique of practical reason (trans: Mary Gregor). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1997b) Lectures on ethics (trans: Peter Heath). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1998) Religion within the boundaries of mere reason (trans: Allen Wood and George di Giovanni). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (2006) Anthropology from a pragmatic point of view (trans: Robert B. Louden). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (1984) Kant’s real self. In: Wood A (ed) Self and nature in Kant’s philosophy. Cornell University Press, Ithaca, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard C (1996) The sources of normativity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Louden RB (2000) Kant’s impure ethics: from rational beings to human beings. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • McGeer V (2007) The moral development of first-person authority. Eur J Philos 81–108

  • Moran R (2001) Authority and estrangement: an essay on self-knowledge. Princeton, Princeton University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill O (1989) Consistency in action. In her Constructions of reason: explorations of Kant’s practical philosophy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sherman N (1993) Wise maxims/wise judging. The Monist, pp 41–65

  • Williams B (1981) Persons, character and morality. In his Moral luck: philosophical papers. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 1–19

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood A (1999) Kant’s ethical thought. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Emer O’Hagan.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

O’Hagan, E. Moral Self-Knowledge in Kantian Ethics. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 12, 525–537 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-009-9181-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-009-9181-7

Keywords

Navigation