Skip to main content
Log in

Understanding Scientific Inquiries of Galileo’s Formulation for the Law of Free Falling Motion

  • Published:
Foundations of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The purpose of this study is to gain a better understanding of the role of abstraction and idealization in Galileo’s scientific inquiries into the law of free falling motion, and their importance in the history of science. Because there is no consensus on the use of the terms “abstraction” and “idealization” in the literature, it is necessary to distinguish between them at the outset. This paper will argue (1) for the importance of abstraction and idealization in physics and the theories and laws of physics constructed with abduction from observations and (2) that these theoretical laws of physics should be tested with deduction and induction thorough quasi-idealized entities rather than empirical results in the everyday world. Galileo’s work is linked to thought experiments in natural science. Galileo, using thought experiments based on idealization, persuaded others that what had been proven true for a ball on an inclined plane would be equally true for a ball falling through a vacuum.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Brown, J. R. (1991). The laboratory of the mind: Thought experiments in the natural science. London & New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. R. (2000). Thought experiments. In W. H. Newton-Smith (Ed.), A companion to the philosophy of science. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, I. B. (1985). The birth of a new physics. New York: W. W. Norton & Company Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drake, S. (1975). Free fall from Albert of Saxony in Honoré Fabri. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 5, 347–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dubin, R. (1978). Theory building. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fernández-González, M. (2013). Idealization in chemistry: Pure substance and laboratory product. Science & Education, 22(7), 1723–1740.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ford, M. S. (2003). Representing and meaning in history and in classrooms: Developing symbols and conceptual organizations of free-fall motion. Science & Education, 12, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galileo, G. (1954). Dialogue concerning two new sciences (H. Crew & A. de Salvio, Trans.). New York: Dover Publications, Inc.

  • Gendler, T. S. (1998). Galileo and the indispensability of scientific thought experiment. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 49, 397–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giancoli, D. C. (1998). Physics: Principles with applications (5th ed.). New Jersey: Prenticle Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gower, B. (1997). Scientific method: An historical and philosophical introduction. New York: Rutledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henry, J. (2012). A short history of scientific thought. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (2002). Understanding philosophy of science. London & New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Losee, J. (2001). A historical introduction to the philosophy of science (4th ed.). New York: Oxford University Press, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L. (1999). Model-based creative abduction. In L. Magnani, N. J. Nersessian, & P. Thagard (Eds.), Model-based reasoning in scientific discovery (pp. 219–238). New York: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L. (2009). Abductive cognition: The epistemological and eco-cognitive dimensions of hypothetical reasoning. Berlin/Heidelberg: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L. (2012). Scientific models are not fictions. Model-based science as epistemic warfare. In L. Magnani & L. Ping (Eds.), Philosophy and cognitive science: Western and Eastern studies (pp. 1–38). Heidelberg/Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McAllister, J. W. (1996). The evidential significance of thought experiment in science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 27, 233–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgeson, F. P., & Hofmann, D. A. (1999). The structure and function of collective constructs: Implication for multilevel research and theory development. Academy of Management Review, 24(2), 249–265.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nola, R. (2004). Pendula, models, constructivism and reality. Science & Education, 13, 349–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. D. (1991). Thought experiments in Einstein’s work. In T. Horowitz & G. J. Massey (Eds.), Thought experiments in science and philosophy (pp. 129–148). Savage, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. D. (1996). Are thought experiments just what you thought? Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 26, 333–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oh, J.-Y. (2012). Understanding scientific inference in the natural sciences based on abductive inference strategies. In L. Magnani & P. Li (Eds.), Philosophy and cognitive science: Western and Eastern studies (pp. 221–237). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Oh, J. Y. (2014). Understanding natural science based on abductive inference: Continental drift. Foundations of Science, 19(2), 153–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ostroff, C., & Bowen, D. E. (2000). Moving HR to a higher level: HR practices and organizational effectiveness. In K. J. Klein & S. W. J. Kozlowski (Eds.), Multilevel theory, research, and methods in organizations: Foundations, extensions, and new directions (pp. 211–266). San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piel, G. (2001). The age of science: What scientists learned in the 20th century. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1978). Peirce’s philosophy of science. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (1988). Computational philosophy of science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trusted, J. (1991). Physics and metaphysics: Theories of space and time. London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Weizsäcker, C. F. (1964). The relevance of science: Creation and cosmogony. New York: Harper and Row, Publishers.

  • Wallis, S. E. (2015). Abstraction and insight: Building better conceptual systems to support more effective social change. Foundations of Science, 20(2), 189–198.

  • Whewell, W. (1847). The philosophy of the inductive sciences. London: John W. Parker.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

For various comments on earlier drafts I am indebted to three reviewers.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jun-Young Oh.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Oh, JY. Understanding Scientific Inquiries of Galileo’s Formulation for the Law of Free Falling Motion. Found Sci 21, 567–578 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-015-9426-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-015-9426-y

Keywords

Navigation