Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-gtxcr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T20:31:45.547Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Real Life, Art, and the Grammar of Feeling

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 January 2009

Oswald Hanfling
Affiliation:
The Open University

Abstract

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Discussion
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1983

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 ‘Fiction and the Suspension of Disbelief’, British Journal of Aesthetics (1978), 31.

2 ‘How Can We be Moved by the Fate of Anna Karenina?’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume (1975).

3 ‘Art and Real Life’, Philosophy (1980). A similar criticism had been made by Radford’s fellow symposiast, MichaelWeston. See Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume (1975).

4 ‘Of Tragedy’, Hume's Essays, J. W. Lenz (ed.), 31-32.

5 Here and elsewhere I am grateful to Colin Radford for comments on an earlier draft.

6 Belief, 307. Price's account is rejected by Schaper.

7 Collingwood emphasized the particularity of such emotions. He argued that only an artist could give them adequate expression; and that‘a genuine poet, in his moments of genuine poetry, never mentions by name the emotions he is expressing’ (p. 112).

8 ‘What is a description of feeling at all? …Discussion of a comedian doing imitations, sketches. Suppose you wanted to describe the experience of the audience—why not describe first of all what they saw?’(Wittgenstein, Lectures and Conversations, 33). One may speak of occasional emotions in terms of either particular occasions or types of occasion. I shall not go into this.