Skip to main content
Log in

Conflict in Medical Co-Production: Can a Stratified Conception of Health Help?

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Health Care Analysis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper considers proposals for developing ‘co-productive’ medical partnerships, within the UK National Health Service (NHS), concentrating in particular on the potential problem involved in combining professional and lay conceptions of health. Much of the literature that advocates the introduction of co-productive healthcare partnerships assumes that medical professionals and patients share, or can easily come to share, a common set of beliefs about what is valuable with regard to health interventions and outcomes. However, a substantial literature documents the contestability of the concept of health, particular across professional and lay divides. We suggest that this potential disagreement ought to be taken seriously, and suggest that the prospect of a co-productive NHS in which patients and professionals act in partnership is threatened by the existence of unresolved epistemic differences. We suggest that part of the solution may lie in re-framing this potential disagreement in the terms provided by Engel’s bio-psycho-social account of health, and demonstrate how support for this account can be grounded upon a critical realist foundation. What we call a ‘stratified conception of health’ reveals the potential complementarity between health beliefs which may have at first seemed to be essentially contradictory. We consider some of the practical implications this idea has for conceiving and creating co-productive medical partnerships.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For example, see Walker [31].

  2. For example, see [11, 12, 29].

  3. See [15, 27].

  4. See [6, 18].

  5. The overarching philosophical system that frames an agent’s beliefs and shapes the manner in which they approach theoretical and practical questions. For more on this, see [4].

  6. For instance, the National Prescribing Centre [22] estimated that 70% of the UK population is taking medicines at any one time to treat or prevent ill-health or to enhance well-being.

  7. This point might be further illustrated by the well established distinction between professional discourses concerning disease and lay discourses concerning illness, for more of which see [16].

  8. For instance, see Bhaskar and Danermark op. cit, p. 287.

  9. Bhaskar [2], p. 36.

  10. For greater exposition of this point see [8].

  11. For instance, see [19, 20].

  12. See [30].

  13. For more on these risks see [17, 21].

References

  1. Bhaskar, R. (1998). The possibility of naturalism. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Bhaskar, R. (2008). A realist theory of science. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Bhaskar, R. (2009). Scientific realism and human emancipation. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Bhaskar, R., & Danermark, B. (2006). Metatheory, interdisciplinarity and disability research: A critical realist perspective. Scandinavian Journal of Disability Research, 8, 278–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Boorse, C. (1977). Health as a theoretical concept. Philosophy of Science, 44, 542–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Bury, M. (1998). Postmodernity and health. In G. Scambler & P. Higgs (Eds.), Modernity, medicine, and health: Medical sociology towards 2000 (pp. 1–29). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Canguilhem, G. (1991). The normal and the pathological. New York: Zone Books.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Danermark, B. (2002). Interdisciplinary research and critical realism: The example of disability research. Alethia, 5, 56–64.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Daniels, N. (1985). Just health care. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  10. Daniels, N. (2008). Just health: Meeting health needs fairly. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Department of Health. (2004). Better information, better choices, better health. London: DH Publications.

  12. Department of Health. (2008). High quality care for all: NHS next stage review final report. London.

  13. Engel, G. L. (1977). The need for a new medical model: A challenge for biomedicine. Science, 196, 129–136.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  14. Groopman, J. E. (2007). How doctors think. New York: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Heath, I. (2003). A wolf in sheep’s clothing: A critical look at the ethics of drug taking. British Medical Journal (Clinical Research Edition), 327, 856–858.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Jennings, D. (1986). The confusion between disease and illness in clinical medicine. Canadian Medical Association Journal, 135, 865–870.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  17. Loewy, E. (2005). In defense of paternalism. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 26, 445–468.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  18. Marinker, M. (1997). Personal paper: Writing prescriptions is easy. British Medical Journal, 314, 747.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  19. Marmot, M. (2005). Social determinants of health inequalities. The Lancet, 365, 1099–1104.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Marmot, M., et al. (2010). Fair society, health lives: Strategic review of health inequalities in England post 2010. London: University College London.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Mol, A. (2008). The logic of care: Health and the problem of patient choice. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  22. National Prescribing Centre. (2007). Introduction to medicines concordance & adherence to treatment. Available online at http://www.npci.org.uk/adherence_to_medicines/atm/intro/workshops/workshop_60minute_elearn_event1.php.

  23. Nordenfelt, L. (1995). On the nature of health: An action-theoretic approach. London: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Royal Pharmaceutical Society of Great Britain. (1997). From compliance to concordance achieving shared goals in medicine taking. London: Royal Pharmaceutical Society.

  25. Sandman, L., & Munthe, C. (2009). Shared decision-making and patient autonomy. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 30(4), 289–310.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  26. Seedhouse, D. (2001). Health: The foundations for achievement (2nd ed.). Chicester: Wiley Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Segal, J. Z. (2007). “Compliance” to “concordance”: A critical view. The Journal of Medical Humanities, 28(2), 81–89.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  28. Shorter, E. (1991). Doctors and their patients: A social history. Piscataway: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Stilgoe, J., & Farook, F. (2008). The talking cure. London: Demos.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Tannen, D. (1998). The argument culture: Moving from debate to dialogue. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Walker, R. (2008). Medical ethics needs a new view of autonomy. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 33(6), 594–608.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  32. Wirtz, V., Cribb, A., & Barber, N. (2007). The use of informed consent for medication treatment in hospital: A qualitative study of the views of doctors and nurses. Clinical Ethics, 2, 36–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. World Health Organization. (1946). WHO definition of health. Available online at: http://www.who.int/about/definition/en/print.html.

  34. World Health Organization. (2003). Adherence to long-term therapies: Evidence for action. Geneva: World Health Organization.

Download references

Acknowledgments

The authors would like to acknowledge the support of the AHRC. This paper was completed whilst John Owens was a Collaborative Doctoral Award holder and Alan Cribb was an AHRC Knowledge Exchange Fellow.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Owens.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Owens, J., Cribb, A. Conflict in Medical Co-Production: Can a Stratified Conception of Health Help?. Health Care Anal 20, 268–280 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10728-011-0186-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10728-011-0186-8

Keywords

Navigation