Skip to main content
Log in

Framing Event Variables

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Davidsonian analyses of action reports like ‘Alvin chased Theodore around a tree’ are often viewed as supporting the hypothesis that sentences of a human language H have truth conditions that can be specified by a Tarski-style theory of truth for H. But in my view, simple cases of adverbial modification add to the reasons for rejecting this hypothesis, even though Davidson rightly diagnosed many implications involving adverbs as cases of conjunct-reduction in the scope of an existential quantifier. I think the puzzles in this vicinity reflect “framing effects,” which reveal the implausibility of certain assumptions about how linguistic meaning is related to truth and logical form. We need to replace these assumptions with alternatives, instead of positing implausible values of event-variables or implausible relativizations of truth to linguistic descriptions of actual events.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Though perhaps given indeterminacy, some class of metalanguage sentences is “the” logical form of S relative to M; see Quine (1960), Davidson (1984). A further complication is that we speak of true friends, true north, and true walls. But I grant that a “semantic” notion of truth, applying to judgments and invented sentences, can be isolated and connected with logic; though see Etchemendy (1990) on the need to avoid implausible model-theoretic conceptions of validity.

  2. We can define ‘logical form’ so that inscription (H) encodes a triviality. But we can also define ‘logical form’ or ‘sentence’ or ‘is’ so that inscription (H) encodes a manifestly false claim. As used here, ‘logical form’—or if you prefer, ‘Logical Form’—is a theoretical term. So one shouldn’t take any proposed definition too seriously. One can say that Human Language sentences do not have compositionally determined meanings that determine logical forms, perhaps because logical forms reflect normative constraints on judgment that are not reflected by those sentences. But then it is misleading to say that Human Language sentences have logical forms, except relative to regimentations; see Quine (1951). By contrast, I think that grammatical form determines logical form, and that (H) should be rejected.

  3. If framing a question one way leads people to endorse a wrong answer that cannot be justified, and framing the question another way leads people to endorse a correct answer that they can justify, then other things equal: frame the question in the first way if you want people to endorse the wrong answer; frame it in the second way if you want people to endorse the correct answer.

  4. For simplicity, assume that no household has more than two children. But it doesn’t matter if there is also a tax deduction for each child beyond the second, perhaps up to some cap, or if we take the “standard household” to have ten children (reducing the base tax and imposing surcharges accordingly). Some descriptions of the policy with lead more people to think/recognize that they have a tax incentive to have more children. But that is part of the point.

  5. Taylor (1985) discusses such examples, citing Christopher Arnold who cited Gareth Evans.

  6. But we cannot identify both stabs with <dawn, Scarlet, Mustard>. More generally, events need to happen at times and have participants, but without being n-tuples of times and participants.

  7. See, e.g., Taylor (1985), Lasersohn (1990), Schein (2002, forthcoming). Plural event descriptions, as in ‘The rocks collided and rained down on the huts’, are beyond the scope of this paper; see Boolos (1998), Lasersohn (1995), Schein (1993), Landman (1996), Pietroski (2005b).

  8. See Schein (2002). Perhaps Alvin did some piano-lifting. But (43) implies that some event was a lifting of the piano by Alvin. Moreover, ‘the piano’ can be replaced with ‘five pianos at once’.

  9. The phrase ‘heard that Mustard yelled’ is different again. If (44) is true, and Mustard was the tallest officer, then Peacocke heard the tallest officer yell. But if she heard that Mustard yelled—say, because Plum passed on the rumor—she need not have heard that the tallest officer yelled.

  10. See Wilson (1989), Ginet (1990), Pietroski (2000). Perhaps (52) and (53) can both used to talk about the relevant “root action,” whatever it turns out to be. Speakers can use expressions to talk about things that the expressions are not true of; see, e.g., Donnellan (1966). One can posit forms like the following: ∃a∃e[R(a, e) & Shot(e, Scarlet, Green)]; where R(a, e) is true of <α, β> if and only if α is the action “at the root of” β. But even if this formal claim is true if and only if Scarlet shot green, this may reflect the metaphysics of shooting, not the meaning of ‘shoot’.

  11. Of course, Simon played the song by playing his tuba, and not vice versa. But this asymmetry, which may well reflect order of intentions, is not yet any reason for distinguishing α from α′; see Anscombe (1957), Thomson (1977), Hornsby (1980).

  12. See especially Tenny (1994) and further references there.

  13. In personal correspondence, Schein says that he finds theses (H) and (D)—from section one—untenable, and that he does not identify meanings with truth conditions. He is, though, inclined to retain a modified version of (H): if S is a sentence of a Human Language, and S* is the logical form of S, then S has no truth condition that deviates from the truth condition if any that S* specifies. This is because Schein takes a logical form to represent both subjective and objective aspects of a speaker’s situation—her mental state and ambient conditions, at a moment of utterance—in a way the capture certain invariance(s) across expressions, thoughts, and contexts; cp note 2 above. See Luldow (2011) for related discussion.

  14. For helpful comments and discussion, my thanks to the conference participants, the PHLING group at Maryland, Norbert Hornstein, Terje Londahl, Georges Rey, Zoltan Szabo, and especially to Barry Schein for many conversations over many years.

References

  • Anscombe, G. (1957). Intention. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boolos, G. (1998). Logic, logic, and logic. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castañeda, H. (1967). Comments. In N. Rescher (Ed.), The logic of decision and action. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1965). Aspects of the theory of syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1977). Essays on form and interpretation. New York: North Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (2000). New horizons in the study of language and mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Costa, M. (1987). Causal theories of action. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 17, 831–854.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1967a). The logical form of action sentences. Reprinted in Davidson 1980.

  • Davidson, D. (1967b). Truth and meaning. Reprinted in Davidson 1984.

  • Davidson, D. (1968). On saying that. Reprinted in Davidson 1984.

  • Davidson, D. (1969). The individuation of events. Reprinted in Davidson 1980.

  • Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on actions and events. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1984). Essays on truth and interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1985). Adverbs of action. In B. Vermazen & M. Hintikka (Eds.), Essays on Davidson: Actions and events. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan, K. (1966). Reference and definite descriptions. Philosophical Review, 75, 281–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowty, D. (1991). Thematic proto-roles and argument selection. Language, 67, 547–619.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Etchemendy, J. (1990). The concept of logical consequence. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1982). Varieties of reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. (1965). Action and responsibility. In M. Black (Ed.), Philosophy in America. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Francken, P., & Lombard, L. (1992). How not to flip the switch with the flood light. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 73, 31–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginet, C. (1990). On action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1970). A theory of human action. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Higginbotham, J. (1983). The logical form of perceptual reports. Journal of Philosophy, 80, 100–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Higginbotham, J. (1985). On semantics. Linguistic Inquiry, 16, 547–593.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hornsby, J. (1980). Actions. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking fast and slow. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., & Tversky, A. (1982). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decisions under risk. Econometrica, 47, 263–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1996). On the reality of cognitive illusions. Psychological Review, 103, 582–591.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (Eds.). (2000). Choices, values and frames. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1976). Events as property exemplifications. In M. Brandt & D. Walton (Eds.), Action theory. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, (1996). Severing the external argument from its verb. In J. Rooryck & L. Zaring (Eds.), Phrase structure and the Lexicon. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, (1979). A puzzle about belief. In A. Margalit (Ed.), Meaning and use. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landman, F. (1996). Plurality. In S. Lappin (Ed.), The handbook of contemporary semantic theory. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lasersohn, P. (1990). Group action and spatio-temporal proximity. Linguistics and Philosophy, 13(2), 179–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lasersohn, P. (1995). Plurality, conjunction and events. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lepore, E., & McLaughlin, B. (Eds.). (1985). Actions and events. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luldow, P. (2011). The philosophy of generative linguistics. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, T. (1990). Events in the semantics of english. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietroski, P. M. (1998). Actions, adjuncts, and agency. Mind, 107, 73–111

  • Pietroski, P. (2000). Causing actions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietroski, P. (2005a). Events and semantic architecture. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietroski, P. (2005b). Meaning before truth. In G. Preyer & G. Peters (Eds.), Contextualism in philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietroski, P. (2008). Minimalist meaning, internalist interpretation. Biolinguistics, 4, 317–341.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietroski, P. (2010). Concepts, meanings, and truth: first nature, second nature and hard work. Mind and Language, 25, 247–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pietroski, P. (2011). Minimal semantic instructions. In C. Boeckx (Ed.), The Oxford handbook on linguistic minimalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietroski, P. (forthcoming). I-Languages and T-sentences. In B. Armour-Garb (Ed.), The relevance of the liar. Oxford University Press.

  • Quine, W. (1951). Two dogmas of empiricism. Philosophical Review, 60, 20–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1905). On denoting. Mind, 14, 479–493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1957). Mr. Strawson on referring. Mind, 66, 385–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schein, B. (1993). Plurals and events. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schein, B. (2002). Events and the semantic content of thematic relations. In G. Preyer & G. Peters (Eds.), Logical form and language (pp. 91–117). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schein, B. (forthcoming). Conjunction reduction redux. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Strawson, P. (1950). On referring. Mind, 59(235), 320–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, B. (1985). Modes of occurrence. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tenny, C. (1994). Aspectual roles and the syntax-semantics interface. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thalberg, I. (1972). Enigmas of agency. London: Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. (1971). Individuating actions. Journal of Philosophy, 68, 771–781.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. (1977). Acts and other events. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. (2008). Normativity. Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1981). The framing of decisions and the psychology of choice. Science, 211, 453–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vlach, F. (1983). On situation semantics for perception. Synthese, 54, 129–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Paul M. Pietroski.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Pietroski, P.M. Framing Event Variables. Erkenn 80 (Suppl 1), 31–60 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-014-9659-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-014-9659-0

Keywords

Navigation