Skip to main content
Log in

The Transcendental Method and (Post-)Empiricist Philosophy of Science

  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Summary

This paper reconsiders the relation between Kantian transcendental reflection (including transcendental idealism) and 20th century philosophy of science. As has been pointed out by Michael Friedman and others, the notion of a “relativized a priori” played a central role in Rudolf Carnap’s, Hans Reichenbach’s and other logical empiricists’ thought. Thus, even though the logical empiricists dispensed with Kantian synthetic a priori judgments, they did maintain a crucial Kantian doctrine, viz., a distinction between the (transcendental) level of establishing norms for empirical inquiry and the (empirical) level of norm-governed inquiry itself. Even though Thomas Kuhn’s theory of scientific revolutions is often taken to be diametrically opposed to the received view of science inherited from logical empiricism, a version of this basically Kantian distinction is preserved in Kuhn’s thought. In this respect, as Friedman has argued, Kuhn is closer to Carnap’s theory of linguistic frameworks than, say, W.V. Quine’s holistic naturalism. Kuhn, indeed, might be described as a “new Kant” in post-empiricist philosophy of science. This article examines, first, the relativization of the Kantian a priori in Reichenbach’s work, arguing that while Reichenbach (after having given up his original Kantianism) criticized “transcendentalism”, he nevertheless retained, in a reinterpreted form, a Kantian-like transcendental method, claiming that the task of philosophy (of science) is to discover and analyze the presuppositions underlying the applicability of conceptual systems. Then, some reflections on Kuhn’s views on realism are offered, and it is suggested that Kuhn (as well as some other influential contributors to the realism debate, such as Hilary Putnam) can be reinterpreted as a (relativized, naturalized) Kantian transcendental idealist. Given the central importance of Kuhnian themes in contemporary philosophy of science, it is no exaggeration to claim that Kantian transcendental inquiry into the constitutive principles of empirical knowledge, and even transcendental idealism (as the framework for such inquiry), still have a crucial role to play in this field and deserve further scrutiny.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Abela, P.: 2002, Kant’s Empirical Realism, Clarendon Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andersen, H.: 2001, On Kuhn, Wadsworth, Belmont, CA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barker, P., Chen, X. and Andersen, H.: 2003, ‘Kuhn on Concepts and Categorization’, in Nickles (2003), pp. 212–245.

  • Becker, K.: 2002, ‘Kuhn’s Vindication of Quine andCarnap’, History of Philosophy Quarterly19, 217–235.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R.: 1928, Der logische Aufbau der Welt. (English translation: it The Logical Structure of the World & Pseudoproblems in Philosophy, trans. by R.A. George, University of California Press, Berkeley & Los Angeles, 1967/1969.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R.: 1950, ‘Empiricism, Semantics and Ontology’, in L. Linsky (ed.), Semantics and the Philosophy of Language, University of Illinois Press, Urbana, 1952/1972, pp. 208–228.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coffa, J.A.: 1991, The Semantic Tradition from Kant to Carnap: To the Vienna Station, Linda Wessels (ed.), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conant, J. and Haugeland, J.: 2000, ‘Editors’ Introduction’, in Kuhn (2000), pp. 1–9.

  • Davidson, D.: 1984, Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation, Clarendon Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • DiSalle, R.: 2002, ‘Reconsidering Kant, Friedman, Logical Positivism, and the Exact Sciences’, Philosophy of Science69, 191–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleck, L.: 1935, Entstehung und Entwicklung einer wissenschaftlichen Tatsache: Eüinfhrung in die Lehre vom Denkstil und Denkkollektiv, L. Schäfer and T. Schnelle (eds.), Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main, 1980.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M.: 1966, The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences, Routledge, London & New York, 2000 (English ed. first published in 1970).

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M.: 1993, ‘Remarks on the History of Science and the History of Philosophy’, in Horwich (1993), pp. 37–54.

  • Friedman, M.: 1997, ‘Philosophical Naturalism’, Proceedings and Addresses of the APA71(2), 7–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M.: 1999, Reconsidering Logical Positivism, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M.: 2000a, A Parting of the Ways: Carnap, Cassirer, and Heidegger, Open Court, Chicago & La Salle, IL.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M.: 2000b, ‘Transcendental Philosophy and A Priori Knowledge: A Neo-Kantian Perspective’, in P. Boghossian and C. Peacocke (eds.), New Essays on the A Priori, Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp. 367–383.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M.: 2001, Dynamics of Reason, CSLI Publications, Stanford, CA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M.: 2002, ‘Kant, Kuhn, and the Rationality of Science’, Philosophy of Science69, 171–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M.: 2003, ‘Kuhn and Logical Empiricism’, in Nickles (2003), pp. 19–44.

  • Giere, R. and Richardson, A. (eds.): 1996, Origins of Logical Empiricism, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gupta, C.: 2002, Realism versus Realism, Rowman & Littlefield, Lanham, MD.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gutting, G.: 2003, ‘Thomas Kuhn and French Philosophy of Science’, in Nickles (2003), pp. 45–64.

  • Hanna, R.: 2001, Kant and the Foundations of Analytic Philosophy, Clarendon Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horwich, P. (ed.): 1993, World Changes: Thomas Kuhn and the Nature of Science, The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA & London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene, P.: 1993, Reconstructing Scientific Revolutions: Thomas S. Kuhn’s Philosophy of Science, transl. by A. T. Levine, The University of Chicago Press, Chicago & London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaila, E.: 1923, ‘Kantia lukiessa’[Reading Kant], Valvoja-Aika1, 190–199.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaila, E.: 1926, Die Prinzipien der Wahrscheinlichkeitslogik, Annales Universitatis Fennicae Aboensis B IV:1, Turku.

  • Kaila, E.: 1979, in R. S. Cohen (ed.), Reality and Experience: Four Philosophical Essays, D. Reidel, Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamlah, A.: 1989, ‘Erläuterungen, Bemerkungen und Verweise zu den Schriften dieses Bandes’, in A. Kamlah and M. Reichenbach (eds.), Hans Reichenbach, Gesammelte Werke 5, Vieweg & Sohn, Braunschweig/Wiesbaden, pp. 371–454.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I.: 1781/1787, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. by N. Kemp Smith, St Martin’s Press, New York, 1965.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koskinen, H.J.: 2004, From a Metaphilosophical Point of View: A Study of W.V. Quine’s Naturalism, Acta Philosophica Fennica 74, The Philosophical Society of Finland, Helsinki.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T.S.: 1970, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd edition, The University of Chicago Press, Chicago & London (1st edition 1962).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T.S.: 2000, in J. Conant and J. Haugeland (eds.), The Road Since Structure: Philosophical Essays, 1970–1993, with an Autobiographical Interview, The University of Chicago Press, Chicago & London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, C.I.: 1923, ‘A Pragmatic Conception of the A Priori’, The Journal of Philosophy20, 169–177.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malpas, J. (ed.): 2003, From Kant to Davidson: Philosophy and the Idea of the Transcendental, Routledge, London & New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manninen, J.: 2002a, ‘Eino Kaila ja tie Wienin piiriin’[Eino Kaila and the Road to the Vienna Circle], Tieteessä tapahtuu2/2002, 34–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manninen, J.: 2002b, ‘Uuden filosofisen liikkeen ja sen manifestin synty’[The Birth of a New Philosophical Movement and Its Manifesto], in I. Niiniluoto and H. J. Koskinen (eds.), Wienin piiri[The Vienna Circle], Gaudeamus, Helsinki, pp. 27–128.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, J.: 1993, The Flux of History and the Flux of Science, University of California Press, Berkeley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, J.: 1995, Historied Thought, Constructed World: A Conceptual Primer for the Turn of the Millennium, University of California Press, Berkeley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (ed.): 2003, Thomas Kuhn, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I.: 1999, Critical Scientific Realism, Oxford University Press, Oxford & New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norris, C.: 2000, Minding the Gap: Epistemology and Philosophy of Science in the Two Traditions, University of Massachusetts Press, Amherst.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oksala, J.: 2002, Freedom in the Philosophy of Michel Foucault, Philosophical Studies from the University of Helsinki 2, Department of Philosophy, University of Helsinki.

  • Pihlström, S.: 1996, Structuring the World: The Issue of Realism and the Nature of Ontological Problems in Classical and Contemporary Pragmatism, Acta Philosophica Fennica 59, The Philosophical Society of Finland, Helsinki.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pihlström, S.: 1998, Pragmatism and Philosophical Anthropology: Understanding Our Human Life in a Human World, Peter Lang, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pihlström, S.: 2003, Naturalizing the Transcendental: A Pragmatic View, Prometheus/Humanity Books, Amherst, NY.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pihlström, S.: 2004, ‘Recent Reinterpretations of the Transcendental’, Inquiry47, 289–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pihlström, S. and Koskinen, H.J.: 2001, ‘Philosophical and Empirical Knowledge in the Program of Naturalism’, in M. Kiikeri and P. Ylikoski (eds.), Explanatory Connections: Essays Dedicated to Matti Sintonen’s 50th Birthday[online],http://www.valt.helsinki.fi/kfil/matti..

  • Putnam, H.: 1981, Reason, Truth and History, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H.: 1983, Realism and Reason, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H.: 1994, Words and Life, ed. J. Conant, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA & London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V.: 1951, ‘Two Dogmas of Empiricism’, in Quine, From a Logical Point of View, revised edition, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1980 (1st edition 1953), pp.20–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H.: 1916, Der Begriff der Wahrscheinlichkeit fuer die mathematische Darstellung der Wirklichkeit, Inaugural-Dissertation, Universität Erlangen, 1915, in A. Kamlah and M. Reichenbach (eds.), Hans Reichenbach. Gesammelte Werke in 9 Bänden, Vieweg & Sohn, Braunschweig/Wiesbaden, Band 5, 1989, pp. 225–292.(Originally published by Barth, Leipzig. Published also in Zeitschrift fuer Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, vol. 161, 210–239; vol. 162, 98–112, 223–253.)

  • Reichenbach, H.: 1920, The Theory of Relativity and A Priori Knowledge, trans. by M. Reichenbach, University of California Press, Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1965. (Originally: Relativitätstheorie und Erkenntnis Apriori, Springer, Berlin.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H.: 1921, ‘The Present State of the Discussion on Relativity’, in M. Reichenbach (ed. & trans.), Modern Philosophy of Science: Selected Essays, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London, 1958, pp. 1–45. (Originally: ‘Der gegenwärtige Stand der Relativitätsdiskussion’’, Logos: Internationale Zeitschrift fuer Philosophie und Kultur10, 316–378.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H.: 1924, Axiomatik der relativistischen Raum-Zeit-Lehre, Vol. 72 of the series Die Wissenschaft, Vieweg, Braunschweig.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H.: 1925, ‘Metaphysics and Natural Science’, in M. Reichenbach and R.S. Cohen (eds.), Hans Reichenbach, Selected Essays: 1909–1953, Reidel, Dordrecht, 1978. (Originally published in Symposiom 1, 158–176.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H.: 1928, Philosophie der Raum-Zeit-Lehre, Walter de Gruyter, Berlin & Leipzig.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H.: 1931, ‘Aims and Methods of Modern Philosophy of Nature’, in M. Reichenbach (ed. & trans.), Modern Philosophy of Science: Selected Essays, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, 1958, pp. 79–108. (Originally published as a booklet under the title Ziele und Wege der heutigen Naturphilosophie, Felix Meiner, Leipzig, 1931).

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H.: 1938, Experience and Prediction: An Analysis of the Foundations and the Structure of Knowledge, The University of Chicago Press, Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H.: 1951, The Rise of Scientific Philosophy, The University of California Press, Berkeley & Los Angeles.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, A.: 1998, Carnap’s Construction of the World: The Aufbau and the Emergence of Logical Empiricism, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rouse, J.: 2003, ‘Kuhn’s Philosophy of Scientific Practice’, in Nickles (2003), pp. 101–121.

  • Scheffler, I.: 1967, Science and Subjectivity, Hackett, Indianapolis, 2nd edition, 1982/1985.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seibt, J.: 2000, ‘Constitution Theory and Metaphysical Neutrality: A Lesson for Ontology?’, The Monist83, 161–183.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sharrock, W. and Read, R.: 2002, Kuhn: Philosopher of Scientific Revolution, Polity Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siitonen, A.: 1997, ‘The Pragmatic Turn in the Light of Reichenbach’s Experience and Prediction’, in P. Weingartner, G. Schurz, and G. Dorn (eds.), The Role of Pragmatics in Contemporary Philosophy: Papers of the 20th International Wittgenstein Symposium, The Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society, Kirchberg am Wechsel, Vol. 2, pp. 903–909.

  • Siitonen, A.: 2002, ‘Looginen empirismi ja Hans Reichenbachin Experience and Prediction’[Logical Empiricism and Hans Reichenbach’s Experience and Prediction], in I. Niiniluoto and H. J. Koskinen (eds.), Wienin piiri[The Vienna Circle], Gaudeamus, Helsinki, pp. 149–167.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sokal, A. and Bricmont, J.: 2003, Intellectual Impostures: Postmodern Philosophers’ Abuse of Science, 2nd edition, Profile Books, London (1st edition in French 1997, in English 1998).

    Google Scholar 

  • Stadler, F.: 1997, Der Wiener Kreis, Springer, Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westphal, K.R.: 2004, Kant’s Transcendental Proof of Realism, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L.: 1953, Philosophical Investigations, trans. G.E.M. Anscombe, Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1958.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sami Pihlström.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Pihlström, S., Siitonen, A. The Transcendental Method and (Post-)Empiricist Philosophy of Science. J Gen Philos Sci 36, 81–106 (2005). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-005-7163-6

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-005-7163-6

Keywords

Navigation