Skip to main content
Log in

Dynamic permissivism

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There has been considerable philosophical debate in recent years over a thesis called epistemic permissivism. According to the permissivist, it is possible for two agents to have the exact same total body of evidence and yet differ in their belief attitudes towards some proposition, without either being irrational. However, I argue, not enough attention has been paid to the distinction between different ways in which permissivism might be true. In this paper, I present a taxonomy of forms of epistemic permissivism framed as the upshot of different ways one might respond to a basic argument against the view from Roger White. I then introduce a new type of permissive view which the contemporary debate has completely ignored and which is made available when we reject a widespread and largely unexamined background commitment to static rational norms connecting beliefs and evidence in favor of dynamic norms governing processes of consideration. I show how the dynamic strategy of rejecting static norms on belief opens the door to a new kind of permissivism which is both independently attractive and especially well-placed to answer worries that have been raised against traditional permissivist views.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Meacham (2013) defends the permissive form of Bayesianism, while Christensen (2007) argues for impermissivism.

  2. For a defense centered on the more moderate versions of permissivism, see Kelly (2010, 2013). Also, Mark Nelson (2010) argues for a moderate view on which withholding judgment is always permissible.

  3. In particular, they suggest that uniqueness precludes both being an internalist about rationality and an externalist about evidence, and being an externalist about rationality and an internalist about evidence.

  4. Some motivations for conservatism can be found in Harman (1986), McGrath (2007).

  5. See, for example, Christensen (2007) on “rational ideals”.

  6. I owe an appreciation of this point to an anonymous referee.

  7. One may be wondering, at this point, whether the sort of considerations just sketched make room for permissive philosophical disagreements. There is some reason to think that the extent to which they do is comparatively limited. This is because for people who are active participants in an academic dispute—it won’t be the case that the agents differ because one of them rationally hasn’t considered the issue, or hasn’t considered it deeply. That comes with the job, so to speak. And those are the main ways in which agents can, on the view described, end up permissibly disagreeing on the same evidence.

  8. On the dynamic view, the disagreement of others might have bearing in at least two ways—first, on whether one reconsiders a question, and as potential evidence during the consideration itself. Plausibly, learning someone, particularly someone who has similar or better evidence, or considered a question as carefully as you did, disagrees with you is a reason to reconsider. And plausibly, the testimony of experts as well as of equals has some evidential force. But this leads us into contentious territory—the overall dynamic permissivist approach is strictly compatible with many different views about the evidential bearing of the beliefs of others.

References

  • Ballantyne, N., & Coffman, E. J. (2011). Uniqueness, evidence, and rationality. Philosopher’s Imprint, 11(18), 1–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broome, J. (2007). Wide or narrow scope. Mind, 116(462), 359–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, D. (1994). Conservatism in epistemology. Noûs, 28, 69–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, D. (2007). Does Murphy’s law apply in epistemology? Oxford Studies in Epistemology, 2, 3–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R. (2007). Reasonable religious disagreement. In L. Antony (Ed.), Philosophers without God (pp. 197–214). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1986). Change in view: Principles of reasoning. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hedden, B. (2015). Time-slice rationality. Mind, 124(494), 449–491.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, T. (2010). Peer disagreement and higher order evidence. In A. Goldman & D. Whitcomb (Eds.), Social epistemology (pp. 183–220). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, T. (2013). Evidence can be permissive. In M. Steup & J. Turri (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (2nd ed.). Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. (1988). Judgement and justification. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGrath, M. (2007). Memory and epistemic conservatism. Synthese, 157(1), 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meacham, C. (2013). Impermissive Bayesianism. Erkenntis, 1–33, 1185–1217.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, M. (2010). We have no positive epistemic duties. Mind, 119, 83–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, G. (2001). Nominalism, naturalism, epistemic relativism. Philosophical Perspectives, 15, 69–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schoenfield, M. (2014). Permission to believe: Why permissivism is true and what it tells us about irrelevant influences on belief. Nous, 48, 193–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (2012). Stakes, withholding, and pragmatic encroachment on knowledge. Philosophical Studies, 160, 265–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sklar, L. (1975). Methodological conservatism. The Philosophical Review, 84(3), 374–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White, R. (2005). Epistemic permissiveness. Philosophical Perspectives, 19(1), 445–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Abelard Podgorski.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Podgorski, A. Dynamic permissivism. Philos Stud 173, 1923–1939 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0585-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0585-z

Keywords

Navigation