Skip to main content

The Semantics of Open Concepts

  • Chapter

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 119))

Abstract

The main problem to be discussed in this paper has a long philosophical tradition. It emerged for the first time in reflections on vague terms in common language. The term (a) ‘youth’ (in the sense of a young man) may serve as a classical example. There is practically no doubt that a man under 18 is still a youth, and that no one over 30 is any longer a youth. But what about a person who is, for instance, 25 years old? The meaning assigned to that term in common language is such that we are not in a position to answer the question. What then is the nature of a statement that a person aged 25 is a youth? Is it a true or a false, but essentially undecidable statement, as some claim ? Or is it deprived of any truth value, as others would have it? Or is it, perhaps, the case that both the statement and its negation are false, as still others maintain, thereby rejecting the principle of the excluded middle — one of the fundamental laws of logic? These questions lead to further questions. What, in fact, is such a statement about? Does the term ‘youth’ denote any definite set of objects ? And if it does, then what is that set?

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. The partial definition of the predicate Q in its general form can be formu lated so as to be a non-creative definition: ∧x ((P1x ∧ ~P2x →Qx) ∧ (P2X ∧ ~ P1x → ~ Qx)). The above definition is logically equivalent to the type (1) statement: ∧x ((P1x ≡ ~ P2x) → (Qx ≡ P1x)).

    Google Scholar 

  2. For a more detailed discussion see M. Przełęcki, ‘Pojecia teoretyczne a do świadczenie’ (Theoretical Concepts and Experience), Studia Logica, XI, 1961, ‘O pojęciu genotypu’ (On the Concept of Genotype), Studia Filozoficzne, 26, 1961.

    Google Scholar 

  3. R. Suszko, ‘Logika formalna a niektóre zagadnienia teorii poznania’ (Formal Logic and Some Problems in Epistemology) Myśl Filozoficzna, 28, 29, 1957.

    Google Scholar 

  4. To simplify matters we are disregarding here those extra-logical expressions which are function symbols. Likewise, the predicates which occur in the examples will always be treated as monadic predicates. But our analysis can easily be generalized so as to cover predicates of n arguments.

    Google Scholar 

  5. A unary relation is identified with a subset of U.

    Google Scholar 

  6. In p1esenting these semantic concepts I have followed R. Suszko’s paper, cited above.

    Google Scholar 

  7. The relativization to language will be omitted in the definitions that follow; we do this to simplify our formulations as far as possible. and will be treated as models of L and L’ respectively. The clause in (EL): D (Q) → (Z(Q) ≡ Z) is true in every model is, of course, equivalent to: for any model if D (Q) is true in, then Z(Q) is true in if and only if Z is true in. We shall refer to the last formulation from time to time.

    Google Scholar 

  8. An analogous result is obtained if instead of Ψ∧ Q we adopt the implication Ψ → Q.

    Google Scholar 

  9. This can be demonstrated more clearly for a case in which Ψ and Q are simple predicates in L, e.g., P1 and P2, so that D (Q) becomes A x (P1x → (Q xP2x)). If = <U, x1, …, xn, X1, …, Xm, Y>, then we take to be <U, x1, …, xn, X1, …, Xm, X2>. It that case the assumption that D (Q) is true in is equivalent to the tautology ∧ xU (xX1 → (xX2xX2)) and as such may be disregarded. On the other hand, the statement that Z(Q) is true in is equivalent to the statement that Z(P2) is true in, and may be replaced by the latter. By way of example let Z(Q) be P1a1Qa1. The latter is true in if and only if x1X1xX2, and hence, if and only if P1a1P2a1in true in

    Google Scholar 

  10. See The Reach of Science, Toronto 1958. A precise analogue of the concept of a “determinate” statement will be introduced later in this paper.

    Google Scholar 

  11. This formulation is equivalent to the condition (EL) as formulated in the text. An analogous observation applies to (ET) and (EM).

    Google Scholar 

  12. To simplify matters, we omit the necessary relativization to language: a statement Z is true in a language L, or in a model of L.

    Google Scholar 

  13. This interpretation of the concepts of proper model and true statement is to be found in R. Suszko’s paper cited above and in J. Kemeny, ‘A New Approach to Semantics’, Journal of Symbolic Logic, 21, 1956.

    Google Scholar 

  14. I discuss the language of empirical theories in my paper Theoretical Concepts and Experience (see footnote2 above), and the ways of interpreting the specific terms of empirical theories, in ‘Interpretacja systemów aksjomatycznych’ (Interpretation of Axiomatic Systems), Studia Filozoficzne, 21, 1960. I have analysed the interpretation of observation terms in ‘O definiowaniu terminów spostrze-żeniowych’ (On Defining Observation Terms), in: Rozprawy logiczne (Papers on Logic). Warsaw 1964.

    Google Scholar 

  15. The set—P2 is the complement of the set P2 to the universe U.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Standpoint (I.I) roughly corresponds to the standpoint I adopt in my paper ‘W sprawie terminów nieostrych’ (Concerning Vague Terms), Studia Logica, VIII, 1958.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Standpoint (I.2) coincides with that adopted by H. Mehlberg in The Reach of Science.

    Google Scholar 

  18. The standpoint (II) approximately corresponds to that adopted by W. Rozeboom in ‘The Factual Content of Theoretical Concepts’. Minnesota Studies … Vol. 3, 1962.

    Google Scholar 

  19. I know of no representative of standpoint (III).

    Google Scholar 

  20. The standpoint adopted by T. Kubiéski in ‘Nazwy nieostre’ (Vague Terms), Studia Logica, VII, 1958, falls within the general outline of standpoint (IV).

    Google Scholar 

  21. Cf. Theoretical Concepts and Experience (see footnote2 above).

    Google Scholar 

  22. This is explicitly stated by H. Mehlberg in his book cited above. Standpoint (V) is an expanded and more precise version of the standpoint which I adopt in Theoretical Concepts and Experience and which is tacitly assumed by many authors.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Both the relative and the absolute concepts of designation and denotation require relativization to a given language, which for simplicity is omitted here.

    Google Scholar 

  24. See footnotes 16 and 18.

    Google Scholar 

  25. See footnotes 17 and 20.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Such a non-classical calculus of terms is constructed by T. Kubiéski in his paper cited above.

    Google Scholar 

  27. The following assumption could be a reason for the adoption of definition (B): P designates x if and only if every onewho correctly uses P can, under specified circumstances, predicate P about x.

    Google Scholar 

  28. The proof given in this paper does not apply to the general case.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Cf. E. Nagel, The Structure of Science, New York 1961.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1979 PWN — Polish Scientific Publishers — Warszawa

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Przelęcki, M. (1979). The Semantics of Open Concepts. In: Pelc, J. (eds) Semiotics in Poland 1984–1969. Synthese Library, vol 119. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-9777-6_27

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-9777-6_27

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-009-9779-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-9777-6

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics