Skip to main content
Log in

Varying versions of moral relativism: the philosophy and psychology of normative relativism

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Among naturalist philosophers, both defenders and opponents of moral relativism argue that prescriptive moral theories (or normative theories) should be constrained by empirical findings about human psychology. Empiricists have asked if people are or can be moral relativists, and what effect being a moral relativist can have on an individual’s moral functioning. This research is underutilized in philosophers’ normative theories of relativism; at the same time, the empirical work, while useful, is conceptually disjointed. Our goal is to integrate philosophical and empirical work on constraints on normative relativism. First, we present a working definition of moral relativism. Second, we outline naturalist versions of normative relativism, and third, we highlight the empirical constraints in this reasoning. Fourth, we discuss recent studies in moral psychology that are relevant for the philosophy of moral relativism. We assess here what conclusions for moral relativism can and cannot be drawn from experimental studies. Finally, we suggest how moral philosophers and moral psychologists can collaborate on the topic of moral relativism in the future.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This is different for meta-ethical relativism: meta-ethical relativism is most often presented or defended in its extreme form, namely that all moral statements are relatively right or wrong if meta-ethical relativism is correct. For a discussion of this view, see Sinnott-Armstrong 2009.

  2. Ethical diversity is here the same as moral diversity. All moral disagreement is an instance of moral diversity but not all moral diversity is an instance of moral disagreement.

References

  • Alas R, Gao JH, Carneiro J (2010) Connections between ethics and cultural dimensions. Inzinerine Ekonomika-Eng Econ 21(3):255–262

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnett T, Bass K, Brown G (1996) Religiosity, ethical ideology, and intentions to report a peer’s wrongdoing. J Bus Ethics 15(11):1161–1174

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bauman CW, Skitka LJ (2009) In the mind of the perceiver: psychological implications of moral conviction. Psychol Learn Motiv: Adv Res theory 50:339–362

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beebe JR (2010) Moral relativism in context. Noûs, 44(4):691–724. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0068.2010.00763.x

  • Benedict R (1934/2001) Anthropology and the abnormal. In: Moser PK, Carson TL (eds) Moral relativism a reader. Oxford University Press: New York/Oxford, pp 79–80

  • Brandt R (1967/2001) Ethical relativism. In: Moser PK, Carson TL (eds) Moral relativism a reader. Oxford University Press, New York/Oxford pp 25–31

  • Campbell RL, Christopher JC (1996) Moral development theory: a critique of its kantian presuppositions. Dev Rev 16(1):1–47

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen SY, Liu CC (2009) Relationships between personal religious orientation and ethical ideologies. Soc Behav Personal 37(3):313–320. doi:10.2224/sbp.2009.37.3.313

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doris JM, Plakias A (2008) How to argue about disagreement: evaluative diversity and moral realism. In: Sinnott-Armstrong W (ed) Moral psychology vol 2 the cognitive science of morality: intuition and diversity. MIT Press, London, pp 303–332

    Google Scholar 

  • Dubinsky AJ, Nataraajan R, Huang WY (2005) Consumers’ moral philosophies: identifying the idealist and the relativist. J Bus Res 58(12):1690–1701. doi:10.1016/j.jbusres.2004.11.002

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Enright R, Lapsley D (1981) Judging others who hold opposite beliefs: the development of belief discrepancy reasoning. Child Dev 52 (3):1053–1063. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1129111

  • Fernando M, Dharmage S, Almeida S (2008) Ethical ideologies of senior australian managers: an empirical study. J Bus Ethics 82(1):145–155. doi:10.1007/s10551-007-9568-0

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan O (1991) Varieties of moral personality ethics and psychological realism. University Press, Harvard

    Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher G (1996) The instability of tolerance. In: Heyd D (ed) Toleration an elusive virtue. Princeton University Press, Princeton, pp 158–172

    Google Scholar 

  • Forsyth (1980) A taxonomy of ethical ideologies. J Person Soc Psychol 39(1):175. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.39.1.175

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forsyth (1992) Judging the morality of business practices—the influence of personal moral philosophies. J Bus Ethics 11(5–6):461–470. doi:10.1007/BF00870557

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forsyth, Berger RE (1982) The effects of ethical ideology on moral behavior. The J Soc Psychol 117(1):53–56. doi:10.1080/00224545.1982.9713406

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forsyth DR, O’Boyle EH, McDaniel MA (2008) East meets west: a meta-analytic investigation of cultural variations in idealism and relativism. J Bus Ethics 83(4):813–833. doi:10.1007/s10551-008-9667-6

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gabennesch H (1990) The perception of social conventionality by children and adults. Child Dev 61(6):2047–2059. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8624.1990.tb03586.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin GP, Darley JM (2008) The psychology of meta-ethics: exploring objectivism. Cognition 106(3):1339–1366. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2007.06.007

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin GP, Darley JM (2010) The perceived objectivity of ethical beliefs: psychological findings and implications for public policy. Rev Philo Psychol 1(2):161–188. doi:10.1007/s13164-009-0013-4

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt J (2001) The emotional dog and its rational tail: a social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychol Rev 108(4):814–834. doi:10.1037//0033-295x.108.4.814

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman G, Thomson JJ (1996) Moral relativism and moral objectivity. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartikainen O, Torstila S (2004) Job-related ethical judgment in the finance profession. J Appl Finance Spring/Summer:62–76

    Google Scholar 

  • Heyd D (ed) (1996) Toleration an elusive virtue. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Huebner B, Lee JJ, Hauser MD (2010) The moral-conventional distinction in mature moral competence. J Cogn Culture 10(1–2):1–26. doi:10.1163/156853710X497149

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly D, Stich S, Haley KJ, Eng SJ, Fessler DMT (2007) Harm, affect, and the moral/conventional distinction. Mind Lang 22(2):117–131. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0017.2007.00302.x

    Google Scholar 

  • Kolodinsky RW, Madden TM, Zisk DS, Henkel ET (2010) Attitudes about corporate social responsibility: business student predictors. J Bus Ethics 91(2):167–181. doi:10.1007/s10551-009-0075-3

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy N (2002) Moral relativism a short introduction. Oneworld Publications

  • Lu LC, Lu CJ (2010) Moral philosophy, materialism, and consumer ethics: an exploratory study in indonesia. J Bus Ethics 94(2):193–210. doi:10.1007/s10551-009-0256-0

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller JG, Bersoff DM, Harwood RL (1990) Perceptions of social responsibilities in India and in the United States: moral imperatives or personal decisions? J Personal Soc Psychol 58(1):33–47. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.58.1.33

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols S (2004) Sentimental rules on the natural foundations of moral judgment. University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols S, Folds-Bennett T (2003) Are children moral objectivists? children’s judgments about moral and response-dependent properties. Cognition 90:B23–B32. doi:10.1016/S0010-0277(03)00160-4

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nucci L, Nucci MS (1982) Children’s responses and social conventional transgressions in free-play settings. Child Dev 53(5):1337–1342 Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1129024

  • Nucci LP, Turiel E (1978) Social interactions and development of social concepts in preschool-children. Child Dev 49(2):400–407 Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1128704

  • Nucci L, Turiel E (1993) God’s word, religious rules, and their relation to christian and jewish children’s concepts of morality. Child Dev 64(5):1475–1491 Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1131547

    Google Scholar 

  • Rest JR (1979) Development in judging moral issues. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, Minnesota

    Google Scholar 

  • Rest JR (1983) Morality. In: Flavell JH, Markman EM (eds) Handbook of child psychology, vol 3: cognitive development. Wiley, New York, pp 556–629

    Google Scholar 

  • Rest JR (1988) Why does college promote development in moral judgement? J Moral Edu 17(3):183–194. doi:10.1080/0305724880170303

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruse M (1986) Evolutionary ethics: a phoenix arisen. Zygon 21:95–112

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sarkissian H, Park J, Tien D, Wright JC, Knobe J (2010) Folk moral relativism. Unpublished manuscript, Baruch College, CUNY

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (1969) Speech acts: an essay in the philosophy of language. Cambridge University Press, England

    Google Scholar 

  • Shweder RA (1990) In defense of moral realism: reply to gabennesch. Child Dev 61(6):2060–2067 Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1130859

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinnott-Armstrong W (2009) Mixed-up meta-ethics. Philo Issues 19(1):235–256. doi:10.1111/j.1533-6077.2009.00168.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smetana JG (1981) Preschool children's conceptions of moral and social rules. Child Dev 52(4):1333–1336 Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1129527

  • Smetana JG (2006) Social-cognitive domain theory: consistencies and variations in children’s moral and social judgments. In: Smetana JG, Killen M (eds) Handbook of moral development. Lawrence Erlbaum Mahwah, NewJersey/London, pp 119–153

    Google Scholar 

  • Sumner WG (1906/2001) Folkways. In: Moser PK, Carson TL (eds) Moral relativism a reader. Oxford University Press, New York/Oxford. pp 69–79

  • Tian Q (2008) Perception of business bribery in china: the impact of moral philosophy. J Bus Ethics 80(3):437–445. doi:10.1007/s10551-007-9429-x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turiel E (1983) The development of social knowledge: morality and convention. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Turiel E, Killen M, Helwig C (1987) Morality. Its structure, functions and vagaries. In: Kagan J, Lamb S (eds) The emergence of morality in young children. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 155–243

    Google Scholar 

  • Vitell SJ, Paolillo JGP (2003) Consumer ethics: the role of religiosity. J Bus Ethics 46(2):151–162

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wainryb C, Shaw LA, Langley M, Cottam K, Lewis R (2004) Children’s thinking about diversity of belief in the early school years: judgments of relativism, tolerance, and disagreeing persons. Child Dev 75(3):687–703. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8624.2004.00701.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winter SJ, Stylianou AC, Giacalone RA (2004) Individual differences in the acceptability of unethical information technology practices: the case of machiavellianism and ethical ideology. J Bus Ethics 54(3):279–301. doi:10.1007/s10551-004-1772-6

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wong DB (1984) Moral relativity. University of California Press, Los Angeles

    Google Scholar 

  • Wong DB (2006) Natural moralities. University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright JC, Cullum J, Schwab N (2008) The cognitive and affective dimensions of moral conviction: Implications for attitudinal and behavioral measures of interpersonal tolerance. Personal Soc Psychol Bull 34(11):1461–1476. doi:10.1177/0146167208322557

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

K.Q. is grateful for the financial support of the Fonds Wetenschappelijk Onderzoek-Vlaanderen. Without implying that they would agree with our perspectives, we thank UCLA’s XBA group, and Stephen Stich, whose ideas helped shape our thoughts on these matters.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Katinka J. P. Quintelier.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Quintelier, K.J.P., Fessler, D.M.T. Varying versions of moral relativism: the philosophy and psychology of normative relativism. Biol Philos 27, 95–113 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-011-9270-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-011-9270-6

Keywords

Navigation