Skip to main content
Log in

Happiness is not Well-Being

  • Research Paper
  • Published:
Journal of Happiness Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper attempts to explain the conceptual connections between happiness and well-being. It first distinguishes episodic happiness from happiness in the personal attribute sense. It then evaluates two recent proposals about the connection between happiness and well-being: (1) the idea that episodic happiness and well-being both have the same fundamental determinants, so that a person is well-off to a particular degree in virtue of the fact that they are happy to that degree, and (2) the idea that happiness in the personal attribute sense can serve as a “proxy” for well-being, i.e., that a person’s degree of deep or robust happiness approximates their degree of well-being. It is argued that happiness in both these senses is conceptually, metaphysically, and empirically distinct from well-being. A new analysis of welfare, well-being as agential flourishing, can explain welfare’s real connection to happiness in both the episodic and personal attribute senses. It predicts that such happiness is only directly beneficial when it is valued, when it is a form of valuing, or when it underwrites (i.e., serves as the causal basis for) the disposition to realize one’s values. It is therefore a necessary—but not sufficient—condition for especially high levels of well-being. This analysis of welfare integrates many insights from the eudaimonic tradition of welfare and happiness research in psychology, and also addresses common criticisms of these eudaimonic models.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Here, the terms “well-being” and “welfare” are used as synonyms, as is common practice in philosophy (see, e.g., Sumner 1996). Both these terms are taken to express the concept of prudential good, i.e., one’s own interests, i.e., personal advantage. This concept is described in more detail at the end of Sect. 2. Philosophical practice, here, differs from practice among those social scientists who use “welfare” as a synonym for “utility,” where this latter is understood as revealed preference-satisfaction (Von Neumann and Morgenstern 1944; Binmore 2009).

  2. This theory attempts to explain the welfare of adult human persons, not the welfare of all possible welfare-subjects or all possible rational beings (it is not clear to me why many philosophers assume that such a general theory of welfare is possible). The theory explains welfare at a time, but it can also be extended to provide estimates of welfare over time and the welfare-ideal human life. It can also be extended to explain the welfare of children. Space limitations prohibit discussion of these extensions, here.

  3. This theory attempts to explain the deep nature of personal benefit and harm; it does not furnish us with any kind of prudential decision-procedure that would allow us to tell which course of action would bring us closer to the paradigm. But, if the theory correctly identifies the “target”—i.e., the deep nature of welfare—psychologists and others who know the relevant empirical facts could presumably identify principles or rules for approaching it.

  4. The disposition to realize one’s values is constituted both by some non-dispositional or “categorical” properties and by some further dispositions; hence the reference to its causal basis rather than its categorical basis (Prior et al. 1982; Fara 2006).

  5. Sen (1985) suggests a different view, one according to which achieved well-being consists partially in achieved functionings, as Nussbaum notes (2011, p. 198).

  6. The emotional state theory does not face the objections Feldman has raised against Davis’s desire-satisfactionist theory, Sumner’s life-satisfaction theory, and Kahneman’s theory of “objective happiness” (Feldman 2010, pp. 37–104). It also has an advantage over Feldman’s own attitudinal hedonism, which does not capture the affective component of episodic happiness. Feldman in fact argues that happiness does not involve any affective component (Cf. Feldman 2010, pp. 143–147). Feldman argues that all a person’s sensory feelings could be suppressed by anesthesia, and yet the person might still be quite happy. The problem with this argument is that Feldman has entirely ignored emotional or affective feelings, which are distinct from sensory feelings like warmth, cold, and pressure. Feldman is correct that it is possible for a person to be attitudinally pleased or happy without having any sensory feelings. But happiness requires the presence of positive emotional states—states which anesthesia does not characteristically suppress. A person who is attitudinally pleased to a high degree without experiencing any of the usual concomitant positive emotional states might count as notionally pleased, but they would not count as happy (cf. Zimmerman 2010).

  7. It is therefore false that, if all of a person’s major goals are being achieved, and a person knows this, then they will simply feel happy as a matter of nomological or causal necessity (cf. Kraut 1979). Even the greatest achievers—those who, against all odds, satisfy all their most important goals—might be afflicted by depression or anxiety and for this reason be seriously unhappy.

  8. Since all the activities rated by this study were ones that subjects picked out as representative of “who [they] are and what [they] are like as a person,” it is also likely that there are other activities that are very enjoyable but that score much lower personal expressiveness, and so are less significant for welfare (just as the present model predicts).

  9. Waterman et al. show empirically that autonomous selection is necessary but not sufficient for activities to exhibit the profile of characteristics usually associated with intrinsically motivated activities. On conceptual grounds, the theory defended here concurs that autonomous selection of goals is not sufficient for them to count as valued, i.e., as objects of pro-attitudes with which the subject stably identifies.

References

  • Annas, J. (1993). The morality of happiness. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arneson, R. (1999). Human flourishing versus desire satisfaction. Social Philosophy and Policy, 16(1), 113–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bentham, J. (1907). Principles of morals and legislation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Binmore, K. (2009). Interpersonal comparisons of utility. In H. Kincaid & D. Ross (Eds.), Oxford handbook of philosophy of economics (pp. 540–559). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Biswas-Diener, R., Kashdan, T. B., & King, L. A. (2009). Two traditions of happiness research, not two distinct types of happiness. Journal of Positive Psychology, 4(3), 208–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bond, E. J. (1988). ‘Good’ and ‘good for’: A reply to Hurka. Mind, 97(386), 279–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1999). Homeostasis, species, and higher taxa. In R. A. Wilson (Ed.), Species: New interdisciplinary essays (pp. 141–185). Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M. (1996). Identification, decision, and treating as a reason. In M. Bratman (Ed.), Faces of intention (pp. 185–206). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, K. W., & Ryan, R. M. (2003). The benefits of being present: Mindfulness and its role in psychological well-being. The Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 84(4), 822–848.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Csíkszentmihályi, M. (1990). Flow: the psychology of optimal experience. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, S. (2002). Welfare and rational care. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. (1981). A theory of happiness. American Philosophical Quarterly, 18(2), 111–112.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deci, E. L., & Ryan, R. M. (2000). The ‘what’ and ‘why’ of goal pursuits: Human needs and the self-determination of behavior. Psychological Inquiry, 11(4), 227–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Della Fave, A., et al. (2011). The eudaimonic and hedonic components of happiness: Qualitative and quantitative findings. Social Indicators Research, 100, 185–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Della Fave, A. et al. (2011b). Hedonism and eudaimonism in positive psychology: Psychological selection and optimal experience across cultures. In A. Della Fave (Ed.), Cross-Cultural Advancements in Positive Psychology 2, 3–18.

  • Diener, E. (2000). Subjective well-being: The science of happiness and a proposal for a national index. American Psychologist, 55(1), 34–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diener, E., & Lucas, R. E. (1999). Personality and subjective well-being. In D. Kahneman, E. Diener, & N. Schwarz (Eds.), Well-being: The foundations of hedonic psychology. New York: Russell Sage Foundation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (1994). Life’s dominion: An argument about abortion and euthanasia. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Easterlin, R. A. (2005). Building a better theory of well-being. In L. Bruni & P. L. Porta (Eds.), Economics and happiness: Framing the analysis (pp. 29–64). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fara, M. (2006). Dispositions. The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. From http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/dispositions/. Accessed June 27, 2011.

  • Feldman, F. (2004). Pleasure and the good life. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, F. (2010). What is this thing called happiness?. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (1998). Identification and wholeheartedness. In H. Frankfurt (Ed.), The importance of what we care about (pp. 159–176). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (2002). Reply to Susan Wolf. In S. Buss & L. Overton (Eds.), Contours of agency. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frederickson, B., & Losada, M. (2005). Positive affect and the complex dynamics of human flourishing. American Psychologist, 60(7), 67–86.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. (1990). Value and justification. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Haybron, D. M. (2008). The pursuit of unhappiness. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heathwood, C. (2006). Desire satisfactionism and hedonism. Philosophical Studies, 128, 547–551.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heathwood, C. (2007). The reduction of sensory pleasure to desire. Philosophical Studies, 133, 23–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hooker, B. (2002). Ideal code, real world. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. (1999). Objective happiness. In D. Kahneman, E. Diener, & N. Schwarz (Eds.), Well-being: The foundations of hedonic psychology (pp. 3–25). New York: Russell Sage Foundation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., Diener, E., & Schwarz, N. (Eds.) (1999). Well-being: The foundations of hedonic psychology. New York: Russell Sage Foundation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kashdan, T. B., Biswas-Diener, R., & King, L. A. (2008). Reconsidering happiness: The costs of distinguishing between hedonics and eudaimonia. Journal of Positive Psychology, 3, 219–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Katz, L. (2008). Pleasure. The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. From http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2003/entries/pleasure/. Accessed June 27, 2011.

  • Keller, S. (2009). Welfare as Success. Nous, 43(44), 656–683.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keyes, C. L. M. (2002). The mental health continuum: From languishing to flourishing in life. Journal of Health and Behavior Research, 43, 207–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keyes, C. L. M. (2007). Promoting and protecting mental health as flourishing. American Psychologist, 62(2), 95–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keyes, C. L. M., Shmotkin, D., & Ryff, C. D. (2002). Optimizing well-being: The empirical encounter of two traditions. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 82(6), 1007–1022.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kraut, R. (1979). Two conceptions of happiness. Philosophical Review, 88, 167–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Larsen, R. J., & Diener, E. (1992). Promises and problems with the circumplex model of emotion. Review of Personality and Social Psychology, 13, 25–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lukas, M. (2010, June). Desire satisfactionism and the problem of irrelevant desires. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy. From http://www.jesp.org/. Accessed June 27, 2011.

  • McMahon, J. (2002). The ethics of killing. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, M. C. (1999). The simple desire-fulfillment theory. Noûs, 33(2), 247–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norton, D. (1976). Personal destinies. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (2006). Frontiers of justice. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (2011). Creating capabilities. Cambridge, Mass: Belknap/Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Prior, E., Pargetter, R., & Jackson, F. (1982). Three theses about dispositions. American Philosophical Quarterly, 19, 251–257.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of ‘meaning’. In H. Putnam (Ed.), Mind, language, and reality. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, J. A. (1980). A circumplex model of affect. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 39, 1161–1178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryan, R. M., & Deci, E. L. (2001). On happiness and human potentials: A review of research on hedonic and eudaimonic well-being. Annual Review of Psychology, 52, 141–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryan, R. M., Huta, V., & Deci, E. L. (2008). Living well: A self-determination theory perspective on eudaimonia. Journal of Happiness Studies, 9, 139–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryff, C. D., & Keyes, C. L. M. (1995). The structure of psychological well-being revisited. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 69(4), 719–727.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryff, C. D., & Singer, B. (1998). The contours of positive human health. Psychological Inquiry, 9(1), 1–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. M. (1998). What we owe to each other. Cambridge, Mass: Belknap/Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seligman, M. E. P. (2011). Flourish: A visionary new understanding of happiness and well-being. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (1985). Well-being, agency, and freedom. Journal of Philosophy, 82, 169–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (1993). Capability and well-being. In A. Sen & M. Nussbaum (Eds.), The quality of life. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (2009). The idea of justice. Cambridge, Mass: Belknap/Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheldon, K. M. (2004). Optimal human being: An integrated multi-level perspective. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sumner, L. W. (1996). Welfare, happiness, and ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tiberius, V. (2008). The reflective life. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tiberius, V., & Hall, A. (2010). Normative theory and psychological research: Hedonism, eudaimonism, and why it matters. Journal of Positive Psychology, 5(3), 212–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Von Neumann, J., & Morgenstern, O. (1944). The theory of games and economic behavior. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waterman, A. (1990). The relevance of Aristotle’s conception of eudaimonia for the psychological study of happiness. Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology, 10(1), 39–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waterman, A. (1993). Two conceptions of happiness: Contrasts of personal expressiveness and hedonic enjoyment. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 64(4), 678–691.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waterman, A. (2008). The implications of two conceptions of happiness for the understanding of intrinsic motivation. Journal of Happiness Studies, 9, 41–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watson, G. (1998). Some considerations in favor of contractualism. In C. Morris & J. Coleman (Eds.), Rational commitment and morality. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1985). Ethics and the limits of philosophy. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1958). Philosophical investigations, 4th edn (P. M. S. Hacker & J. Schulte, Trans.). Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

  • Zimmerman, M. J. (2010). Review of what is this thing called happiness? Resource document. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. From http://ndpr.nd.edu/review.cfm?id=20367. Accessed June 27, 2011.

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Fred Feldman, Dan Haybron, Alan Waterman, the editor of this journal, and two anonymous referees for helpful feedback on the ideas in this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jason R. Raibley.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Raibley, J.R. Happiness is not Well-Being. J Happiness Stud 13, 1105–1129 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10902-011-9309-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10902-011-9309-z

Keywords

Navigation