Skip to main content
Log in

A social epistemology of aesthetics: belief polarization, echo chambers and aesthetic judgement

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

How do we form aesthetic judgements? And how should we do so? According to a very prominent tradition in aesthetics it would be wrong to form our aesthetic judgements about a particular object on the basis of anything other than first-hand acquaintance with the object itself (or some very close surrogate) and, in particular, it would be wrong to form such judgements merely on the basis of testimony. Further this tradition presupposes that our actual practice of forming aesthetic judgements typically meets, or at least approximates, this ideal. In this paper I target this descriptive claim and argue—by appeal to some empirical work concerning belief polarization and echo chambers in aesthetics—that our actual practice of forming aesthetic judgements is heavily dependent on social sources such as testimony. I then briefly consider what normative implications this descriptive claim may have.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Similar thoughts are expressed in Coady (1992: 6–14) and Hopkins (2011: 138).

  2. In this paper I will assume that aesthetic judgements (that is judgements of aesthetic or artistic value) are beliefs and that they are differentiated from other judgements by their content rather than by some special mode of judging. For defences of these claims see Hopkins (2011: 140–141), Meskin (2004: 69) and Livingston (2003: 267–271).

  3. Hopkins (2007: 611) introduces ‘optimism’ and ‘pessimism’ as terms for normative positions regarding moral testimony.

  4. Defences of normative pessimism include Hopkins (2011) and Wollheim (1980: 233). Defences of normative optimism include Meskin (2004 and manuscript), Laetz (2008) and Robson (2013). For discussion of the descriptive view see Meskin (2004: 66) and Laetz (2008: 361–362).

  5. I borrow the term from Sperber (1990).

  6. This strikes me, for instance, as being the case with respect to the study by Ginsburgh and Ours (2003) which illustrates all of my key points with respect to echo chambers in aesthetics.

  7. Hopkins (2011: 139–142) appears to take appeals to such principles as constitutive of pessimism but I think this further claim is mistaken (for reasons outlined in Robson 2012: 2–3).

  8. Note that the Acquaintance Principle requires not only that individuals have first-hand experience of a work but that their judgements are based on that experience. In a number of the cases I will consider below subjects meet the first condition but fail to meet the second.

  9. McGrath (2011: 115) presents a parallel argument with respect to deference in the moral realm.

  10. http://www.guardian.co.uk/world/2006/mar/25/arts.artsnews.

  11. A sign proclaiming as much, accompanied by a dead shark formerly displayed in a London electronics shop, was prominently displayed in the Stuckist International Gallery.

  12. For detailed accounts of belief polarisation see Kelly (2008) and Lord et al. (1984).

  13. For a more complete description of the experimental set up see (Ibid. 340–344).

  14. Even the normative pessimist will typically allow that others praising a work can legitimately give me some-perhaps, as Hopkins (2011: 154) claims, only pro tempore-reason for thinking that it will be superior to a work which others have condemned.

  15. The fact that the highest and lowest ranked songs were downloaded most is significant since subjects tended to listen to many more songs than they downloaded and to give the songs they downloaded ratings (on a ‘love it’ to ‘hate it’ scale) which were significantly above average (Ibid. 345).

  16. For more detailed accounts see (Jamieson and Cappella (2008): 75–90) and Gilbert et al. (2009).

  17. All quotes from Bredius are taken from Werness (1983: 31).

  18. Something similar holds in other cases of artistic fakery; it was, for example, no coincidence that Max Harris was chosen as the recipient of the Ern Malley poems (see Heyward 1993: 10–27).

  19. Joseph Duveen quoted in Wynne (2006: 152).

  20. Similarly Harris’ initial praise of the Malley poems could hardly have been more unrestrained (see Heyward 1993: xvi).

  21. Kilbracken quoted in Werness (1983: 51).

  22. Nor a more modest version of descriptive pessimism which permits, as many versions of normative pessimism e.g. those of Hopkins (2011: 154) and Wollheim (1980: 233) do, some limited exceptions.

  23. Most of the literature (e.g. Loftus 1975) focuses on misinformation but, as Michaelian (2013) discusses at length, a parallel phenomenon arises with accurate testimonial inputs.

  24. Work on this paper was supported by a generous grant from the Arts and Humanities Research Council of the United Kingdom. An earlier version of this paper was presented at the fourth Lund/Copenhagen Workshop in Social Epistemology and I offer my thanks to the audience at this meeting for their extremely helpful feedback. Special thanks go to Frank Zenker and Carlo Proietti for useful discussion (and exemplary organisation) at the workshop and for subsequent comments on later versions of the paper. Thanks also to Carl Baker, Greg Currie, Aaron Meskin and two anonymous referees.

References

  • Bredius, A. (1937). A new Vermeer. Burlington Magazine, 61, 145.

  • Coady, C. A. J. (1992). Testimony a philosophical study. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cutting, J. E. (2003). Gustave Caillebotte, French impressionism, and mere exposure. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 10, 319–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dutton, D. (2009). The art instinct. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, E., Bergstrom, T., & Karahalios, K. (2009). Blogs are echo chambers: Blogs are echo chambers. In Proceedings of HICSS ’09. 42nd Hawaii international conference on system sciences (pp. 1–10)

  • Ginsburgh, V. A. (2003). Awards, success and aesthetic quality in the arts. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 17, 99–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ginsburgh, V. A., & van Ours, J. C. (2003). Expert opinion and compensation: Evidence from a musical competition. American Economic Review, 93, 289–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heath, J., & Potter, A. (2004). The rebel sell why culture can’t be jammed. Toronto: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heath, C., Berger, J., & Ho, B. (2006). Divergence in cultural practices: Tastes as signals of identity. Working paper.

  • Hess, E. H. (1965). Attitude and pupil size. Scientific American, 212, 46–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heyward, M. (1993). The Ern Malley affair. London: Faber and Faber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hills, A. (2009). Moral testimony and moral epistemology. Ethics, 120, 94–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, R. (2007). What is wrong with moral testimony? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 74, 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, R. (2011). How to be a pessimist about aesthetic testimony. Journal of Philosophy, 108, 138–157.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jamieson, K. H., & Cappella, J. N. (2008). Echo chamber. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Johnstone, J., & Katz, E. (1957). Youth and popular music: A study in the sociology of taste. American Journal of Sociology, 17, 569–578.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1790/2005). Critique of judgement (translated by J.H. Bernard). New York: Dover

  • Kelly, T. (2008). Disagreement, dogmatism, and belief polarization. Journal of Philosophy, 105, 611–633.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kruger, J., & Dunning, D. (1999). Unskilled and unaware of it: How difficulties in recognizing one’s own incompetence lead to inflated self-assessments. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 77, 1121–1134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lackey, J. (2006). Knowing from testimony. Philosophy Compass, 1, 432–448.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laetz, B. (2008). A modest defense of aesthetic testimony. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 66, 355–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, K., Gonzalez, M., & Kaufman, J. (2012). Social selection and peer influence in an online social network. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 109, 69–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Livingston, P. (2003). On an apparent truism in aesthetics. British Journal of Aesthetics, 43, 260–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loftus, E. F. (1975). Leading questions and the eyewitness report. Cognitive Psychology, 7, 560–572.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lord, C. G., Lepper, M. R., & Preston, E. (1984). Considering the opposite: A corrective strategy for social judgment. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 47, 1231–1243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGrath, S. (2011). Skepticism about moral expertise as a puzzle for moral realism. Journal of Philosophy, 108, 111–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meskin, A. (2004). Aesthetic testimony: What can we learn from others about beauty and art? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 69, 65–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meskin, A. (Manuscript). Aesthetic unreliability.

  • Meskin, A., Phelan, M., Moore, M., & Kieran, M. (2013). Mere exposure to bad art. British Journal of Aesthetics, 53(2), 139–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, K. (2013). The information effect: Constructive memory, testimony, and epistemic luck. Synthese, 190, 2429–2456.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • North, A. C., & Hargreaves, D. J. (1999). Music and adolescent identity. Music Education Research, 1, 75–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plassmann, H., O’Doherty, J., Shiv, B., & Rangel, A. (2008). Marketing actions can modulate neural representations of experienced pleasantness. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 105, 1050–1054.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robson, J. (2012). Aesthetic testimony. Philosophy Compass, 7(1), 1–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robson, J. (2013). Aesthetic testimony and the norms of belief formation. European Journal of Philosophy. doi:10.1111/ejop.12007.

  • Salganik, M., & Watts, D. (2008). Leading the herd astray: An experimental study of self-fulfilling prophecies in an artificial cultural market. Social Psychology Quarterly, 71, 338–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D. (1990). The epidemiology of beliefs. In C. Fraser & G. Geskell (Eds.), Psychological studies of widespread beliefs (pp. 25–44). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarrant, M., North, A., & Hargreaves, D. (2001). Social categorization, self-esteem, and the estimated musical preferences of male adolescents. The Journal of Social Psychology, 141, 565–581.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trivers, R. (2011). Deceit and self-deception. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1974). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Science, 185, 1124–1131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Werness, H. (1983). Hans van Meegeren Fecit. In D. Dutton (Ed.), The Forger’s art: Forgery and the philosophy of art (pp. 1–57). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. A. O. (1972). Knowledge and reasons. In G. H. Von Wright (Ed.), Problems in the theory of knowledge (pp. 1–11). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wollheim, R. (1980). Art and its objects (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wynne, F. (2006). I was Vermeer. London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jon Robson.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Robson, J. A social epistemology of aesthetics: belief polarization, echo chambers and aesthetic judgement. Synthese 191, 2513–2528 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0437-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0437-y

Keywords

Navigation