Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

The Role of Research Ethics Committees in Making Decisions About Risk

  • Published:
HEC Forum Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Most medical research and a substantial amount of non-medical research, especially that involving human participants, is governed by some kind of research ethics committee (REC) following the recommendations of the Declaration of Helsinki for the protection of human participants. The role of RECs is usually seen as twofold: firstly, to make some kind of calculation of the risks and benefits of the proposed research, and secondly, to ensure that participants give informed consent. The extent to which the role of the REC includes the former is not uncontroversial. Indeed, the most prevalent debate on the role of RECs sees liberals and strong paternalists arguing over the importance of informed consent given by competent agents versus the significance of making benevolent decisions on behalf of others. On the one hand, liberals argue for the rights of competent adults to decide for themselves the kinds and extents of risks to which they wish to expose themselves. On the other hand, proponents of strong paternalism raise concerns about the likelihood of participants being able to truly understand the complex data involved in research. They support a role for RECs in which they exercise duties of benevolence towards patients and participants by limiting the extent to which they can be exposed to significant, permanent and irreversible harms. In this paper, we will argue that when it comes to decisions about risk it is neither possible nor desirable for RECs to adopt either role.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. World Medical Association (1964).

  2. Athanassoulis and Ross (2010, p. 219).

  3. We are assuming in this paper that death, particularly unexpected death, is usually a kind of harm. We are aware that in some contexts this assumption is controversial and that there exists a long tradition of questioning whether death can constitute a harm because it leaves the dead person incapable of suffering. However, in the context of the topic of this paper we believe our assumption represents a widely accepted, and intuitively plausible, view.

  4. Moral hazard is a term borrowed from economic theory—it arises when someone is likely to take a risk because they are not the ones who will sustain losses that may result. An interesting history of the term and its use can be found in Rowell and Connelly (2012, pp. 1051–1075).

  5. The classic work in psychology on this topic has been done by Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky. See Kahneman and Tversky (1982).

  6. Slovi (2010, pp. 96–109).

  7. Sunstein (2002a, pp. 156–171) and Sunstein (2002b, pp. 33–49).

  8. A number of theories might support such a view of governments, from an Aristotelian conception of the state as a collection of individuals trying to lead eudaimon lives, to conceptions of the state as facilitators of economic activity.

  9. Garrard and Dawson (2005, p. 421).

  10. Garrard and Dawson (2005, p. 420).

  11. The Medicines for Human Use (Clinical Trials) Regulations (2004, p. 20).

  12. Edwards et al. (2004). For a more detailed discussion of the role of inducements see Grant and Sugarman (2004).

  13. Kahneman et al. (1982).

  14. Edwards et al. (2004).

  15. Garrard and Dawson (2005, p. 423).

  16. Ross and Athanassoulis (2010a, b), Athanassoulis and Ross (2010) and Ross and Athanassoulis (2012).

  17. Athanassoulis and Ross (2010, p. 149f).

  18. Ross and Athanassoulis (2012).

  19. Generally, but again not inevitably, taking a risk is easier to justify when doing so is the only option for achieving a good or avoiding a harm, and conversely if risk taking is one of many options it is a lot more difficult to justify the decision to do so.

  20. For more on these and other objective circumstances of risk see Athanassoulis and Ross (2010).

  21. Athanassoulis and Ross (2010).

  22. Angell et al. (2006).

  23. Rational choice theory is an economic theory designed to explain the choices/behaviour of persons in a market, the origins of which are sometimes accredited to Adam Smith’s An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations. Simply put, according to the ‘rational choice model’ a risk is well taken when the expected value multiplied by the probability of the desired outcome is higher than the (expected value X probability) of all other possible outcomes. In economics, expected values are often given in monetary terms. The important point for our purposes is that rational choice models rely on expected rather than realised values. This initially simple theory has been adjusted and developed over the years to try and accommodate anomalies that seem to arise when decisions are made under conditions of uncertainty. A good general summary of the evolution of rational choice thinking can be found in Kreps (1988).

  24. We use brackets to indicate the very narrow sense of ‘rational’ used in rational choice theory, also sometimes referred to as ‘instrumental rationality’.

  25. US Federal Policy for the Protection of Human Subjects, par 46.111(a)(2).

  26. World Health Organisation (2000).

  27. World Medical Association (2000).

  28. European Clinical Trials Directive (2001).

  29. European Forum for Good Clinical Practice (1997)

  30. World Medical Association (2013).

  31. European Clinical Trials Directive (2001).

  32. European Forum for Good Clinical Practice (1997).

  33. Rajczi (2004, pp. 338–348).

  34. Happich et al. (2009, pp. 88–95).

  35. Weijer (2000, p. 344).

  36. Weijer (2000, p.356).

  37. Rajczi (2004, p. 342).

  38. Ideal Observer theory is a well-established doctrine within normative ethics. Ideal observers or choosers are generally taken to be impartial (disinterested and dispassionate), rational (excellent deliberators) and to have ‘a good grasp of all the relevant non-moral facts’. The typical philosophical objections to such theories are that the standards they set are both unachievable—particularly impartiality (Friedman 1989; Young 1990, pp. 104–105)—and undesirable (Wolf 1982, 1992).

  39. For more on this see Ross and Athanassoulis (2012).

  40. For more on this see Ross and Athanassoulis (2012).

  41. Kerrison and Pollock (2005, p. 487).

  42. Ashcroft et al. (2005, p. 587).

  43. Annas (2011, p. 130). For more on all these ideas see Annas, Chapter 8.

  44. Aristotle (2013).

  45. For more on these Aristotelian ideas see Nussbaum (1986), Chapter 11.

  46. We are grateful to an anonymous reviewer for very helpful comments on an earlier version of this paper.

References

  • Angell, E., Sutton, A. J., Windridge, K., & Dixon-Woods, M. (2006). Consistency in decision making by research ethics committees: A controlled comparison. Journal of Medical Ethics, 32, 662–664.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Annas, J. (2011). Intelligent virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Aristotle. (2013). Poetics (A. Kenny, Trans.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Ashcroft, R. E., Newson, A. J., & Benn, P. M. W. (2005). Reforming research ethics committees. British Medical Journal, 331, 587–588.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Athanassoulis, N., & Ross, A. (2010). The social nature of engineering and its implications for risk taking. Science and Engineering Ethics, 16(1), 147–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edwards, S. J. L., Kirchin, S., & Huxtable, R. (2004). Research ethics committees and paternalism. Journal of Medical Ethics, 30, 88–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • European Clinical Trials Directive 2001/20/EC

  • European forum for good clinical practice, (1997). Guidelines and Recommendations for European Ethics Committees, Section B, par ii, p. 11.

  • Friedman, M. (1989). The impracticality of impartiality. Journal of Philosophy, 86, 645–656.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garrard, E., & Dawson, A. (2005). What is the role of the research ethics committee? Paternalism, inducements, and harm in research ethics. Journal of Medical Ethics, 31, 419–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grant, R. W., & Sugarman, J. (2004). Ethics in human subjects research: Do incentives matter? Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 29(6), 717–738.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Happich, M., Moock, J., & von Lengerke, T. (2009). Health state valuation methods and reference points: The case of tinnitus. Value in Health, 12(1), 88–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1982). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. In P. Slovic & A. Tversky (Eds.), Judgement under uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases Kahneman. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., Tversky, A., & Slovic, P. (1982). Judgement under uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kerrison, S., & Pollock, A. M. (2005). The reform of UK research ethics committees: Throwing the baby out with the bath water? Journal of Medical Ethics, 31, 487–489.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kreps, D. (1988). Notes on the theory of choice. Boulder CO: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (1986). The fragility of goodness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rajczi, A. (2004). Making risk-benefit assessments of medical research protocols. Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics, 32, 338–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1983). Risk: A philosophical introduction to the theory of risk evaluation and management. UPA.

  • Ross, A., & Athanassoulis, N. (2010). A virtue ethical account of making decisions about risk. Journal of Risk Research, 13(2), 217–230

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, A., & Athanassoulis, N. (2010b). A virtue ethical account of making decisions about risk. Journal of Risk Research, 13(2), 217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, A., & Athanassoulis, N. (2012). Virtue ethics and risk. In S. Roesner (Ed.), The Handbook of Risk Theory. New York: Springer.

  • Rowell, D., & Connelly, B. (2012). A history of the term moral hazard. The Journal of Risk and Insurance, 79(4), 1051–1075.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slovic, P. (2010). Cigarette smokers: Rational actors or rational fools? In The feeling of risk: New perspectives on risk perception (pp. 96–109). Oxford: Earthscan.

  • Sunstein, C. (2002a). Moral Heuristics and risk. In T. Lewens (Ed.), Risk: Philosophical perspectives (pp. 156–171). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C. (2002b). Risk and reason: Safety, law and the environment (pp. 33–49). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • The Medicines for Human Use (Clinical Trials) Regulations. (2004). Governance Arrangements for Research Ethics committees, The Department of Health, https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/213753/dh_133993.pdf. Accessed January 19, 2013.

  • Weijer, C. (2000). The ethical analysis of risk. Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics, 28, 344–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, S. (1982). Moral saints. Journal of Philosophy, 89, 419–439.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, S. (1992). Morality and partiality. Philosophical Perspectives, 6, 243–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • World Health Organisation. (2000). “Operational guidelines for ethics committees that review biomedical research”, par 6.2.1.2.

  • World Medical Association. (1964). Declaration of Helsinki. Japan: Tokyo.

    Google Scholar 

  • World Medical Association. (2000). Declaration of Helsinki. Edinburgh: World Medical Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • World Medical Association. (2013). Declaration of Helsinki, Fortaleza, Brazil, pars. 16–17.

  • US Federal Policy for the Protection of Human Subjects, par 46.111(a)(2).

  • Young, I. M. (1990). Justice and the politics of difference (pp. 104–105). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Allison Ross.

Additional information

Allison Ross and Nafsika Athanassoulis are independent scholars.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ross, A., Athanassoulis, N. The Role of Research Ethics Committees in Making Decisions About Risk. HEC Forum 26, 203–224 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-014-9244-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-014-9244-6

Keywords

Navigation