Skip to main content
Log in

Generic versus single-case causality: the case of autopsy

  • Original Paper in Philosophy of Science
  • Published:
European Journal for Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper addresses questions about how the levels of causality (generic and single-case causality) are related. One question is epistemological: can relationships at one level be evidence for relationships at the other level? We present three kinds of answer to this question, categorised according to whether inference is top-down, bottom-up, or the levels are independent. A second question is metaphysical: can relationships at one level be reduced to relationships at the other level? We present three kinds of answer to this second question, categorised according to whether single-case relations are reduced to generic, generic relations are reduced to single-case, or the levels are independent. We then explore causal inference in autopsy. This is an interesting case study, we argue, because it refutes all three epistemologies and all three metaphysics. We close by sketching an account of causality that survives autopsy—the epistemic theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Note the change from population-level variables—literacy rate and proportion of immigrants—to individual-level variables—being literate, being an immigrant.

  2. This fact—that frequency is at root a generic relation—also motivates some accounts where levels are metaphysically independent, a position discussed below. In fact, it is not difficult to find cases where at the generic level the causal relatum is, say, a negative causal factor, and yet there exist single cases where an instantiation of the same causal relatum is instead a positive causal factor. This situation has led some authors to argue that the probabilistic account is not undermined by such cases, provided that distinct concepts of cause at work at distinct levels be defined. A stock example in the philosophical literature is the golf ball example mentioned in Section 2. See, for instance, Sober (1984, 1986), Salmon (1980, 1984), Eells (1991), and (Russo 2009, ch. 2 and 6) for a discussion.

  3. It is worth noting that in the account of Lewis (1973), truth conditions of counterfactuals are given in terms of similarity of worlds, and although similarity is not fully explicated in Lewis but taken as a primitive notion, it remains possible that the single-case causal relation depends on generic facts.

  4. Cartwright’s capacity view of causality is close to the complex-systems mechanism view in important respects: complex-systems mechanisms and nomological machines are both conceived of as the underlying physical structures that are responsible for regularities, and they are responsible for those regularities in virtue of the way their components are organised and the behaviour that these components can engage in (Glennan 1996; Bechtel and Abrahamsen 2005; Machamer et al. 2000; Cartwright 1999). But there are differences—for example, the behaviour of the components is variously underwritten by capacities (which are a special sort of dispositional property), activities (which differ from capacities in that they can be relational rather than monadic, and are manifestations rather than dispositions), or laws. The capacity theory maintains that an effect can only be regularly produced by a cause in the context of a nomological machine, so the theory may be classed as a mechanistic theory of causality. It cannot be classed as a difference-making theory because an entity can have a capacity to make no difference: a homeostatic mechanism has the capacity to maintain the status quo; a teenager has the capacity to do nothing. To discover a causal regularity we need to establish the underlying mechanism rather than establish that the cause makes a difference to its effects: ‘we have to establish the arrangement and capacities of mechanical elements and the right shielding conditions that keep the machine running properly’ (Cartwright 1999, p. 50).

  5. There are exceptions such as Glennan (2002), discussed below. Note however that several accounts that apparently appeal to both aspects simultaneously do not on closer inspection. While apparently appealing to both mechanisms and counterfactuals, Glennan (2010) is in fact pluralist, while for Craver counterfactuals are used as tests. Glennan (2010) distinguishes two concepts: (i) causal relevance and (ii) causal production. On the one hand, a property, in his account, is causally relevant to an event if the event counterfactually depends on the property; on the other hand, an event causally produces another if they are connected by a chain of causal processes. (In fact for Glennan, mechanisms are truthmakers for both kinds of causal claim.) In Craver’s account, counterfactuals do not enter the definition of ‘mechanism’ but are rather used to evaluate causal claims. Indeed, Craver (2007, ch. 4) does not mention any counterfactual element in the features of mechanisms; on the contrary, he stresses—e.g., Craver (2007, p. 64, 65, 86)—that counterfactuals and manipulations serve to evaluate causal mechanisms; that is to say, counterfactuals are tests, not definers.

  6. The proponent of the mechanistic analysis might argue that difference-making evidence can help establish the existence of a mechanism. But it still remains the case that according to this sort of position, once the mechanism is established no further difference-making evidence is required. It is this last point that we contest (Russo and Williamson 2007).

  7. It is worth noting that Hill never considered his points as ‘criteria’ but just as guidelines. However, this is not relevant to our argument, which is just to point out what ‘elements’ are required to establish causal claims.

  8. Of course, as to how to characterise the ideal causal epistemology is open to some speculation. In Williamson (2005) a hybrid of hypothetico-deductive and inductive epistemology is proposed and in Russo (2009) it is argued that the epistemic theory is compatible with a variational epistemology. A variational epistemology says, simply put, that reasoning underlying the discovery and confirmation of causal relations hinges on the notion of variation. A variational epistemology is not confined to either level—generic or single-case. Quite to the contrary, it can be shown that the concept of variation plays a role in causal discovery and confirmation at the generic level as well as in the single-case (Russo 2009, ch. 7). This means that a ‘level-monism’ does not enter from the back door—the epistemic theory does not require an epistemology that is ‘single-level’, so to speak.

  9. Note that, in the light of the epistemic theory, the standard classification of theories of causality into difference-making and mechanistic theories is in fact somewhat blurred. The epistemic theory is neither classifiable as purely mechanistic nor as purely difference-making. Hence the two categories are not mutually exclusive and exhaustive.

References

  • Abdel-Karim, I. A., Sammel, R. B., & Prange, M. A. (2007). Causes of death at autopsy in an inpatient hospice program. Journal of Palliative Medicine, 10(4), 894–898.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adams, V. I. (2008). Guidelines for reports by autopsy pathologists. Humana Press.

  • Aho, H. (2003). The roles of autopsies in the development of medicine. Duodecim, 119(13), 1255–1264 (article in Finnish).

    Google Scholar 

  • Ayoub, T., & Chow, J. (2008). The conventional autopsy in modern medicine. Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine, 101, 177–181.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2005). Explanation: A mechanist alternative. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 36, 421–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1989). Nature’s capacities and their measurement. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1999). The dappled world: A study of the boundaries of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, L. B., Amsel, G., Redford, M. A., & Casasola, M. (1998). The development of infant causal perception. In A. Slater (Ed.), Perceptual development: Visual, auditory, and speech perception in infancy (pp. 167–209). East Sussex: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, H., Leigh, M. A., Lucas, S., & Martin, I. (2007). The coroner’s autopsy. The final say in establishing cause of death? The Medico Legal Journal, 75, 114–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the brain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cummings, P. M., Le, B. H., & Lopes, M. B. S. (2007). Postmortem findings in morbidly obese individuals dying after gastric bypass procedures. Human Pathology, 38(4), 593–597.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dieboled, J. (2007). Clinical autopsy—its role in modern medicine. Praxis (Bern 1994), 96(43), 1667–1671 (article in German).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowe, P. (2000). Physical causation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ducasse, C. J. (1926). On the nature and the observability of the causal relation. The Journal of Philosophy, 23(3), 57–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ducasse, C. J. (1968). Truth, knowledge and causation. New York: Humanities.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eells, E. (1991). Probabilistic causality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fornaro, G., Lazzero, M., Giacalone, A., Aralda, D., Prando, M. D., Rossi, L., et al. (2008). Death after ST-elevation myocardial infarction in patients treated with fibrinolytic therapy, angioplasty, or conventional therapy. A post-mortem study to verify cardiac rupture as a cause of death. Giornale italiano di cardiologia, 9(6), 408–420 (article in Italian).

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerring, J. (2005). Causation: A unified framework for the social sciences. Journal of Theoretical Politics, 17, 163–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillies, D. A. (2011). The Russo–Williamson thesis and the question of whether smoking causes heart disease. In P. McKay Illari, F. Russo, & J. Williamson (Eds.), Causality in the sciences. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (1996). Mechanisms and the nature of causation. Erkenntnis, 44, 49–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (2002). Rethinking mechanistic explanation. In Philosophy of science. Supplement: Proceedings of the 2000 biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association. Part II: Symposia papers (Sep. 2002) (Vol. 69(3), pp. S342–S353).

  • Glennan, S. (2010). Mechanisms, causes and the layered model of the world. Philosophy & Phenomenological Research, 81(2), 362–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, N. (2004). Two concepts of causation. In J. Collins, N. Hall, & L. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals (pp. 225–276). The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hill, B. (1965). The environment and disease: Association or causation? Proceedings of the Royal Society of Medicine, 58, 295–300.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1748). Enquiry into the human understanding. In Enquiries concerning human understanding and concerning the principles of morals (1777 ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Izegbu, M. C., Agboola, A. O. J., Shittu, L. A. J., & Akiode, O. (2006). Medical certification of death and indications for medico-legal autopsies: The need for inclusion in continue medical education in Nigeria. Scientific Research and Essay, 1(3), 61–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jönssona, A. K., Holmgrenb, P., Druid, H., & Ahlner, J. (2007). Cause of death and drug use pattern in deceased drug addicts in Sweden, 2002–2003. Forensic Science International, 169(2–3), 101–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A. M., & Keeble, S. (1987). Do six-month-old infants perceive causality? Cognition, 25, 265–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1973). Causation. In Philosophical papers (Vol. 2, pp. 159–213). Oxford: Oxford University Press (1986).

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, P. (2008). Coroners’ law resource. http://www.kcl.ac.uk/depsta/law/research/coroners/.

  • Michotte, A. (1962). The perception of causality. Andover, MA: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Muentener, P., & Carey, S. (2006). What is the domain of causal perception? Investigating causal perception of motion and non-motion state change events in infancy. Journal of Vision, 6, 965a.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • NCEPOD (2006). The coroner’s autopsy: Do we deserve better? http://www.ncepod.org.uk/2006.htm. National Confidential Enquiry into Patient Outcome and Death.

  • NCHS (2003). Physicians’ handbook on medical certification of death. National Center for Health Statistics, Hyattsville, Maryland.

  • Ní Bhrolcháin, M., & Dyson, T. (2007). On causation in demography: Issues and illustrations. Population and Development Review, 33(1), 1–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2004). A glimpse of the secret connexion: Harmonising mechanisms with counterfactuals. Perspectives on Science, 12(3), 288–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, W. S. (1950). Ecological correlations and the behavior of individuals. American Sociological Review, 15, 351–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roulson, J., Benbow, E. W., & Hasleton, P. S. (2005). Discrepancies between clinical and autopsy diagnosis and the value of post mortem histology; a meta-analysis and review. Histopathology, 47, 551–559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russo, F. (2009). Causality and causal modelling in the social sciences. Measuring variations. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Russo, F., & Williamson, J. (2007). Interpreting causality in the health sciences. International Studies in Philosophy of Science, 21(2), 157–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. C. (1980). Probabilistic causality. In Causality and explanation (pp. 208–232). Oxford: Oxford University Press (1988).

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. C. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton University Press.

  • Salmon, W. C. (1998). Causality and explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sando, Z., Borisch, B., & Bosman, F. (1999). Autopsies: From the past to the future. Revue Médicale de la Suisse Romande, 119(10), 763–767 (article in French).

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlottmann, A., & Surian, L. (1999). Do 9-month-olds perceive causation-at-a-distance? Perception, 28, 1105–1113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shojania, K. G., Burton, E. C., McDonald, K. M., & Goldman, L. (2003). Changes in rates of autopsy-detected diagnostic errors over time: A systematic review. Journal of the American Medical Association, 289(21), 2849–2856.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1984). Two concepts of cause. In PSA: Proceedings of the biannual meeting of the philosophy of science association (1982) (Vol. 2, pp. 405–424).

  • Sober, E. (1986). Causal factors, causal inference, causal explanation. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, 60, 97–113.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swaen, G., & van Amelsvoo, L. (2009). A weight of evidence approach to causal inference. Journal of Clinical Epidemiology, 62(3), 270–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taggart, M. W., & Craver, R. (2006). Causes of death, determined by autopsy, in previously healthy (or near-healthy) children presenting to a children’s hospital. Archives of Pathology and Laboratory Medicine, 130(12), 1780–1785.

    Google Scholar 

  • Terrabuio, Jr., A. A., Parra, E. R., Farhat, C., & Capelozzi, V. L. (2007). Autopsy-proven causes of death in lungs of patients immunocompromised by secondary interstitial pneumonia. Clinical Sciences, 62(1), 69–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsokos, M., Heinemann, A., & Püschel, K. (2000). Pressure sores: Epidemiology, medico-legal implications and forensic argumentation concerning causality. International Journal of Legal Medicine, 113(5), 283–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Twardy, C. R., & Bingham, G. P. (2002). Causation, causal perception, and conservation laws. Perception & Psychophysics, 64, 956–968.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ullah, K., & Alamgir, W. (2006). Comparison of clinical causes of death with autopsy diagnosis using discrepency classification. Journal of College of Physicians and Surgeons Pakistan, 16(12), 768–772.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, E. (2007). Conceptual tools for causal analysis in the social sciences. In F. Russo & J. Williamson (Eds.), Causality and probability in the sciences (pp. 197–213). London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, J. (2005). Bayesian nets and causality: Philosophical and computational foundations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, J. (2006a). Causal pluralism versus epistemic causality. Philosophica, 77, 69–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, J. (2006b). Dispositional versus epistemic causality. Minds and Machines, 16, 259–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, J. (2007). Causality. In D. Gabbay & F. Guenthner (Eds.), Handbook of philosophical logic (Vol. 14, pp. 95–126). Springer.

  • Williamson, J. (2009). Probabilistic theories of causality. In H. Beebee, C. Hitchcock, & P. Menzies (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of causation (pp. 185–212). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, J., & Gabbay, D. (2005). Recursive causality in Bayesian networks and self-fibring networks. In D. Gillies (Ed.), Laws and models in the sciences (pp. 173–221). London: King’s College Publications (with comments pp. 223–245).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This research was supported by funds from the British Academy and the Fonds Nationale de Recherche Scientifique (Belgium). We are grateful to Alan Bates, Nancy Cartwright, Brendan Clarke, Carl Hoefer and an anonymous referee for very helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Federica Russo.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Russo, F., Williamson, J. Generic versus single-case causality: the case of autopsy. Euro Jnl Phil Sci 1, 47–69 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-010-0012-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-010-0012-4

Keywords

Navigation