Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

An Axiomatic Theory of Law

  • Published:
Res Publica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper presents in outline Luigi Ferrajoli’s axiomatic and general theory of law, as developed in his lifelong work Principia Iuris. The first section focuses on the three main aspects of the theory: the methodological, the theoretical and the pragmatic, which respectively represent the theory’s syntax, semantics and its pragmatics. Ferrajoli identifies three deontic gaps of norms: firstly, the one between their validity and efficacy; secondly, the one between their justice and validity; and finally, and most importantly, the one between validity and existence (i.e. normative force). The presence of such gaps is, according to Ferrajoli, the extraordinary innovation that entrenched constitutions have brought into modern legal systems, by establishing norms that are superior to statutes and case law. In this sense, all normative phenomena (except for the constitution itself) can be conceived both as norms and as facts. In the second section the role of juridical science is briefly discussed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. From now on, this text will be referred as PI. Unless otherwise indicated, page references in brackets will be to volume I of the book.

  2. In this sense, Ferrajoli’s theory of law is the result of calculus. The first volume of PI is the ‘translation’ in plain language of the more formal reasoning of volume 3. For a description of the axiomatic method, cf. Varga 2009, pp. 17–18.

  3. In particular, Hughes and Cresswell’s system S5 plus Barrican’s formula.

  4. I owe this remark to G.B. Ratti, and his presentation ‘Ferrajoli’s Juridical Logic’ at a Workshop at the University of Edinburgh Spring Programme in Legal Theory, in June 2010.

  5. This is also a point made by G.B. Ratti, see n. 4 above.

  6. This is a consequence of the relationship between the intension and the extension of such a theory (3–11).

  7. According to Ferrajoli, the distinction between legal theory and dogmatics lies in their different methodological status. Concepts of dogmatics are obtained by lexical reformulations of the empirical legal language, i.e. the language used by statutes, judges, academics, and so on. Concepts belonging to legal theory are conventionally defined by the theorists themselves, according to their fruitfulness.

  8. As such, they cannot be a priori established—thus they will change from system to system.

  9. This is possible thanks to the distinction Ferrajoli draws between a legal act and its meaning, i.e. the norm produced by such an act.

  10. Although it could be said that Ferrajoli defines the ‘province’ of the problem; he does not directly engage with the ‘topographic’ tools, that is, the tools of formal logic. In PI, he does not mention, for instance, the defeasible character of legal norms and the problems it bears. On this, cf. Ferrer Beltràn and Ratti (2010).

  11. [Editor’s Note: As Ferrajoli explains in his contribution to this symposium, principia iuris tantum are principles external to positive law while principia iuris et in iure are principles internal to positive law].

  12. Ferrajoli is keen to point out the conventional character of the choices made by the theorists in the first place—some of which can of course be politically, but also morally, related.

  13. According to Ferrajoli, Guastini and many others, this is the biggest flaw in Kelsen’s theory, namely the fact that he does not account for this meta-theoretical duplicity of constitutional legal systems.

  14. Compare it with what Opalek and Wolenski (1975) define, in negative terms, as the ‘substantial overextension’ between the axiomatisation and the underlying system.

References

  • Alchourrón, Carlos E., and Eugenio Bulygin. 1971. Normative systems. Springer: Vienna.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Beltràn, Jordi Ferrer, and Ratti, Giovanni B. 2010. Validity and defeasibility in the legal domain. Law and Philosophy 29: 601–626.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bobbio, Norberto. 1988. Reason in law. Ratio Juris 1: 97–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bulygin, Eugenio. 2008. What can one expect from logic in the law? (Not everything, but more than something: A reply to Susan Haack). Ratio Juris 21: 150–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, Rudolf. 1958. Beobachtungssprache und theoretische Sprache. Dialectica 12: 236–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald. 1986. Law’s empire. London: Fontana Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferrajoli, Luigi. 2007. Principia iuris, vol. I, Teoria del diritto. Roma-Bari: Laterza.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, Thomas F. 1994. From Jhering to Alexy–using artificial intelligence models in jurisprudence. Legal knowledge based system. In JURIX 94: The foundation for legal knowledge systems, ed. H. Prakken, A.J. Muntjewerff, and A. Soeteman, 19–32. Lelystad: Koninklijke Vermande.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guastini, Riccardo. 2009. Garantismo e dottrina pura a confronto. Analisi e Diritto 21: 213–223.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haack, Susan. 2007. On logic in the law: Something, but not all. Ratio Juris 20: 1–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, Herbert L.A. 1961. The concept of law. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, Hans. 1915. Eine Grundlegung der Rechssoziologie. Archiv für Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik 39: 839–876.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, Hans. 1967. Pure theory of law. (trans: Knight, M.). Berkeley: University of California Press.

  • Klug, Ulrich. 1982. Juristische Logik. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1989. [1670–1671], In Elementa juris naturalis, English translation, ed. Leroy Loemker, Elements of natural law. Philosophical papers and letters, 131–138. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Leiter, Brian. 2003. Beyond the Hart/Dworkin debate: The methodology problem in jurisprudence. American Journal of Jurisprudence 48: 17–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morris, Charles. 1938. Foundations of the theory of signs. International encyclopedia of unified science, ed. Otto Neurath, vol. 1 no. 2. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Rpt in Morris, Charles, 1971. Writings on the general theory of signs, pp. 13–71. The Hague: Mouton.

  • Opalek, Kazimierz, and Wolenski, Jan. 1975. Das Problem der Axiomatisierung des Rechts. In Rechtstheorie und Rechtsinformatik, ed. Gunther Winkler, 51–66. Wien-New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Paulson, Stanley L. 1993. Continental normativism and its British counterpart: How different are they? Ratio Juris 6: 227–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perry, Stephen R. 2001. Hart’s methodological positivism. In Hart’s postscript: essays on the postscript to the concept of law, ed. J. Coleman, 311–354. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pino, Giorgio. 1999. The place of legal positivism in contemporary constitutional states. Law and Philosophy 18: 513–536.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prakken, Henry. 1997. Logical tools for modelling legal argument. A study of defeasible reasoning in law. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rödig, Jurgen. 1980. Schriften zur juristischen Logik. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Supiot, Alain. 2007. Homo juridicus. On the anthropological function of the law. London-New York: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varga, Csaba. 2009. The quest for formalism in law. Ideals of systemicity and axiomatisability between utopianism and heuristic assertion. Acta Juridica Hungarica 50: 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Villa, Vittorio. 1997. Legal theory and value-judgments. Law and Philosophy 16: 447–477.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

My warm thanks go to Giorgio Pino, Giovanni Battista Ratti and in particular to Francisco Saffie Gatica for valuable comments on a previous draft of this paper, and to Patricia Armstrong for checking over my English. I remain the only one responsible for every error or omission in this piece.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Paolo Sandro.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Sandro, P. An Axiomatic Theory of Law. Res Publica 17, 343–354 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-011-9168-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-011-9168-9

Keywords

Navigation