Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Beyond words: linguistic experience in melancholia, mania, and schizophrenia

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, we use a phenomenological approach to compare the unusual ways in which language can be experienced by individuals with schizophrenia or severe mood disorders, specifically mania and melancholia (psychotic depression). Our discussion follows a tripartite/dialectical format: first we describe traditionally observed distinctions (i.e., decrease or increase in amount or rate of speech in the affective conditions, versus alterations of coherence, clarity, or interpersonal anchoring in schizophrenia); then we consider some apparent similarities in the experience of language in these conditions (e.g., striking disorganization of manic as well as schizophrenic speech, interpersonal alienation in both schizophrenia and severe depression). Finally, we explore more subtle, qualitative differences. These involve: 1, interpersonal orientation (less concern with the needs of the listener in schizophrenia), 2, forms of attention and context-relevance (e.g., manic distractibility versus schizophrenic loss of orientation), 3, underlying mutations of experience (e.g., sadness/emptiness in melancholia versus disturbances of basic selfhood in schizophrenia), and 4, meta-attitudes toward language (i.e., greater alienation from language-as-such in schizophrenia). Such distinctions appear to reflect significant differences in underlying forms of subjectivity; they are broadly consistent with work in phenomenological psychopathology on other aspects of experience, including body, self, and social world. An understanding of such distinctions may assist with difficult cases of differential diagnosis, while also contributing to a better understanding of suffering persons and of psychological factors underlying their disorders.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We thank two anonymous reviewers for their astute suggestions on revising this paper.

  2. For a parallel discussion, but more focused on the experience of other persons in melancholia, mania, and schizophrenia, see Sass and Pienkos (under review). For comparative discussions of self-experience and world-experience (time, space, atmosphere), see Sass and Pienkos (2013a, b).

  3. This paragraph is nicely summed up in philosopher Merleau-Ponty’s (1945/1962) lapidary statement: “The spoken word is a gesture, and its meaning a world.”

  4. A shared feature of our experience of both language and other persons is that both are intimately bound up with the phenomenon of “expression”—viz, with the manifestation of thoughts and feelings and their communication to others, whether by word, facial expression, or bodily tension or movement. As Sartre, Levinas, and other philosophers have pointed out, expression implies something that is both immanent and transcendent, both present and beyond. Words, like faces, have a certain sensory presence, visual or auditory; but in both cases this presence directs our attention inward as well as outward—inward toward what is presumed to be a grounding awareness or emanating consciousness, outward toward the meanings or worldly objects that are being indicated. Jean-Paul Sartre (1966) described the face as a “visible transcendence”; in similar fashion, a word, as normally experienced, can be considered an “audible transcendence.” In this sense both a word and a face—at least as normally experienced—share a certain “aura”: that of a sensory presence whose immediacy always points beyond. Emmanuel Levinas (1969) argues that a face is authentically a face only if it is recognized as comprising an “infinity” and not a “totality,” which is to say, as something whose meanings are rich and ambiguous enough to transcend any single interpretation by the viewer. In the absence of the above-mentioned aura, one may feel oneself in the presence of something uncanny, e.g., of behavior that is somehow other than fully human, or a sound that functions as something far less, or far more, than a word.

  5. As noted, one perennial issue is whether there is indeed a sharp diagnostic distinction between schizophrenia and affective psychosis, or whether these conditions exist more on a continuum (Dutta et al. 2007; Tsuang and Simpson 1984) or perhaps constitute a more heterogeneous assortment.

  6. Such a comparison may also have relevance for psychotherapy or other psychological treatments. A better understanding of possible ways of experiencing language in psychopathology should help in developing empathy and improving one’s therapeutic alliance with a patient—as well as in accurately targeting specific areas of interpersonal experience for intervention. The relationship between therapist and patient, largely linguistic or linguistically mediated, is, of course, a primary tool for bringing about change in these domains. With greater understanding of the attitudes these patients may adopt and the challenges they may face in using and understanding language, one may be in a better position to develop sensitive and effective interventions—interventions less likely to be undermined by failure to grasp some of the very issues they are intended to target and treat.

  7. Together with colleagues (Borut Skodlar, Josef Parnas, Nev Jones), we are currently preparing a qualitative interview schedule, the Examination of Anomalous World Experience or EAWE, which is modeled on the well-known EASE: Examination of Anomalous Self Experience (Parnas et al. 2005). The EAWE will contain a major section focusing on the subjective experience of language, both productive and receptive; this should facilitate one form of empirical research on the topic.

  8. See Sass et al. (2011) re the rejection, in most contemporary phenomenology, of “foundationalist” claims.

  9. Even the philosopher Daniel Dennett, a neo-behaviorist, acknowledges in his discussion of (so-called) “heterophenomenology” that descriptions of experience, properly criticized, can “inspire, guide, motivate, illuminate one’s scientific theory” (Dennett 2003, p. 23).

  10. Kant’s famous line from the Critique of Pure Reason (1855), “Thoughts without content are empty, intuitions without concepts are blind” (A51, B75), has been glossed more or less as paraphrased above in General Systems (General systems 1962).

  11. We borrow this phrase from Trow (1997), who used it in a rather different context.

  12. In his early work, the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, Wittgenstein (1922) argued against the possibility of this sort of all-encompassing statement as well.

  13. We would disagree with Lacan’s (1981/1993) claim that this rejection (of the symbolic order, or what he calls the “nom du père”) is a factor for psychosis in general; rather it seems characteristic of schizophrenia in particular.

  14. This is Jared Loughner, the young man who shot several people in Tucson in an attack on a local congresswoman, Gabrielle Giffords, on January 8, 2011. We are relying on a television report from 60 Minutes which included an interview with several of Loughner’s close friends who describe his behavior and attitudes from before the shooting (Descent into Madness 2011). Loughner was subsequently diagnosed as having schizophrenia and declared unfit to stand trial.

References

  • Akiskal, H. (2009). Mood disorders: Clinical features. In B. J. Sadock, V. A. Sadock, & P. Ruiz (Eds.), Kaplan and Sadock’s comprehensive textbook of psychiatry (9th ed., pp. 1693–1733). Philadelphia, PA: Lippincott Wlliams & Wilkins.

    Google Scholar 

  • American Psychiatric Association (2000). Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, 4th Edn, Text Revision. Arlington, VA: American Psychiatric Association.

  • Andreasen, N. C. (1979). Thought, language, and communication disorders. Archives of General Psychiatry, 36, 1315–1330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andreasen, N. (1986). Scale for the assessment of thought, language, and communication (TLC). Schizophrenia Bulletin, 12(3), 473–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andreasen, N., & Grove, W. M. (1986). Thought, language, and communication in schizophrenia: diagnosis and prognosis. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 12(3), 348–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benveniste, E. (1958/1971). Subjectivity in language. In E. Benveniste (Ed.), Problems in General Linguistics. (trans: Meek, M.E.) (pp. 223–230). Miami: University of Miami Press.

  • Bleuler, E. (1950). Dementia Praecox or the Group of Schizophrenias (trans: Zinkin, J.). New York: International Universities Press.

  • Bleuler, M. (1982). Inconstancy of schizophrenic language and symptoms. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 5, 591.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bovet, P., & Parnas, J. (1993). Schizophrenic delusions: a phenomenological approach. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 19(3), 579–597.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Casey, M. (2002). A better place to live. In N. Casey (Ed.), Unholy ghost: Writers on depression (pp. 281–293). New York: Harper Perennial.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (1995). Facing up to the problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2, 200–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad, K. (1958/1997). La esquizofrenia incipiente. (Orig. Die beginnende Schizophrenie: Versuch einer Gestaltanalyse des Wahns.) (trans: Belda, J.M. & Rabano, A.). Trans. J.M. Belda and A. Rabano. Madrid: Fundación Archivos de Neurobiologia.

  • Covington, M., He, C., Brown, C., Lorina, N., McClain, J., & Fjordbak, B. (2005). Schizophrenia and the structure of language: the linguist’s view. Schizophrenia Research, 77(1), 85–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crow, T. J. (2000). Schizophrenia as the price that homo sapiens pays for language: a resolution of the central paradox in the origin of the species. Brain Research Reviews, 31, 118–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crow, T. J. (2002). Bipolar shifts as disorders of the bi-hemispheric integration of language. In A. Marneros & J. Angst (Eds.), Bipolar Disorders: 100 Years after Manic-Depressive Insanity. New York: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cutting, J. (1985). The Psychology of Schizophrenia. Oxford, England: Churchill Livingstone.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cutting, J. (1997). Principles of Psychopathology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Decker, B., & Van de Craen, P. (1987). Towards and interpersonal theory of schizophrenia. In R. Wodack & P. Van de Craen (Eds.), Neurotic and psychotic language behaviour (pp. 249–265). Clevedon, England: Multilingual Matters.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (2003). Who’s on first? Heterophenomenology explained. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10(9–10), 19–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descent into Madness. (2011). 60 Minutes: CBS News.

  • Dutta, R., Greene, T., Addington, J., McKenzie, K., Phillips, M., & Murray, R. M. (2007). Biological, life-course, and cross-cultural studies all point toward the value of dimensional and developmental ratings in the classification of psychosis. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 33(4), 868–876.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elvevåg, B., Fisher, J., Gurd, J., & Goldberg, T. (2002). Semantic clustering in verbal fluency: Schizophrenic patients versus control participants. Psychological Medicine, 32, 909–917.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ey, H. (1996). Schizophrénie: Études cliniques et psychopathologiques. Paris: Synthelabo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fink, M., & Taylor, M. A. (2007). Resurrecting melancholia. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica, 115(S433), 14–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, T. (2005). Corporealized and disembodied minds: a Phenomenological view of the body in melancholia and schizophrenia. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology, 12(2), 95–107.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garnham, A., & Oakhill, J. (1994). Language and thought. In Thinking and reasoning (pp. 42–56). Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greden, J. F., & Carroll, B. J. (1980). Decrease in speech pause times with treatment of endogenous depression. Biological Psychiatry, 15(4), 575–587.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, G., Huber, G., Klosterkotten, J., & Linz, M. (2008). Bonn Scale for the Assessment of Basic Symptoms. Aachen, Germany: Shaker Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, A., Watkins, E., Mansell, W., & Shafran, R. (2004). Cognitive behavioural processes across psychological disorders: A transdiagnostic approach to research and treatment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Holzman, P. S., Shenton, M. E., & Solovay, M. R. (1986). Quality of thought disorder in differential diagnosis. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 12(3), 360–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hyman, S. E. (2010). The diagnosis of mental disorders: the problem of reification. Annual Review of Clinical Psychology, 6, 155–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jamison, K. R. (1995). An unquiet mind. New York: Random House, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaspers, K. (1946/1963). General psychopathology. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

  • Kant, I. (1855). Critique of pure reason. London: Henry G. Bohn.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, B. (Ed.). (1964). The inner world of mental illness. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kraepelin, E. (1919/1971). Dementia Praecox and Paraphrenia. (trans: Barclay, R.M.). Huntington, NY: Robert E. Krieger.

  • Kraepelin, E. (1920/1974). Patterns of mental disorder. In S. R. Hirsch, & M. Shepherd (Eds.), Themes and Variations in European Psychiatry, (trans: Marshall, H.) (pp. 7–30). Bristol: Wright.

  • Kuperberg, G. (2006). Building the linguistic context in schizophrenia: evidence from self-paced reading. Neuropsychology, 20(4), 442–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lacan, J. (1981/1993). The seminars of Jacques Lacan: Book III the psychoses, 1955–1956. New York: W.W. Norton.

  • Laing, R. D. (1965). The divided self. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lake, C. R. (2008). Disorders of thought are severe mood disorders: the selective attention defect in mania challenges the Kraepelinian dichotomy–a review. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 34(1), 109–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laruelle, F. (1978). Au-delà du principe de pouvoir. Paris: Payot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lecours, A. R., & Vanier-Clement, M. (1976). Schizophasia and jargonaphasia. Brain and Language, 3, 516–565.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, E. (1969). Totality and Infinity. Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liddle, P., & Barnes, T. (1988). The subjective experience of deficits in schizophrenia. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 29(2), 157–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lott, P. R., Guggenguhl, S., Schneeberger, A., Pulver, A. E., & Stassen, H. H. (2002). Linguistic analysis of the speech output of schizophrenic, bipolar, and depressive patients. Psychopathology, 35, 220–227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matussek, P. (1987). Studies in delusional perception. In J. Cutting & M. Shepherd (Eds.), The clinical roots of the schizophrenia concept. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1945/1962). Phenomenology of Perception. New York: Routledge.

  • Minkowski, E. (1927/2012). La schizophrénie (excerpt). In M. R. Broome, R. Harland, G. S. Owen, & A. Stringaris (Eds.), The Maudsley Reader in Phenomenological Psychiatry (pp. 143–155). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

  • Møller, P., & Husby, R. (2000). The initial prodrome in schizophrenia: searching for naturalistic core dimension of experience and behavior. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 26(1), 217–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1979). Mortal questions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parnas, J., & Bovet, P. (1991). Autism in schizophrenia revisited. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 32(1), 7–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parnas, J., Moller, P., Kircher, T., Thalbitzer, J., Jansson, L., Handest, P., et al. (2005). EASE: examination of anomalous self-experience. Psychopathology, 38, 236–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, W. A., & Silverstein, S. M. (2003). Impaired cognitive coordination in schizophrenia: convergence of neurobiological and psychological perspectives. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 26, 65–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radden, J., & Varga, S. (2013). The epistemological value of depression memoirs: A meta-analysis. In K. Fulford, M. Davies, R. Gipps, G. Graham, J. Sadler, G. Stanghellini, et al. (Eds.), Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Psychiatry (pp. 99–115). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Rosenman, S., Korten, A., Medway, J., & Evans, M. (2003). Dimensional vs. categorical diagnosis in psychosis. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica, 107, 378–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosser, R. (1979). The psychopathology of feeling and thinking in a schizophrenic. International Journal of Psychoanalysis, 60, 177–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J. P. (1966). Faces, preceded by Official Portraits. In M. Natanson (ed.), Essays in Phenomenology (pp. 157–163). The Hague: M. Nijhoff.

  • Sass, L. A. (1992). Madness and modernism: Insanity in the light of modern art, literature, and thought. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sass, L. A. (1994). The paradoxes of delusion: Wittgenstein, Schreber, and the schizophrenic mind. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sass, L. A. (1995). Antonin Artaud, modernism, and the yearning for a “private language”. In K. Johannesen & T. Nordenstam (Eds.), Culture and value (papers from 18th International Wittgenstein Symposium) (pp. 255–260). Kinrchberg, Austria: Austiran Ludwig Wittgenstein Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sass, L. A. (2004). Schizophrenia: A disturbance of the thematic field. In L. Embree (Ed.), Gurwitch’s relevancy for the cognitive sciences (pp. 59–78). Dordrecht, Holland: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sass, L. A. (2013). Self-disturbance and schizophrenia: structure, specificity, pathogenesis (Current issues, new directions). Schizophrenia Research. doi:10.1016/j.schres.2013.05.017.

  • Sass, L. A., & Parnas, J. (2003). Schizophrenia, consciousness, and the self. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 29(3), 427–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sass, L. A., & Pienkos, E. (2013a). Varieties of self-experience: a comparative phenomenology of melancholia, mania, and schizophrenia, Part I. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 20(7–8), 103–130.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sass, L. A., & Pienkos, E. (2013b). Space, time, and atmosphere: a comparative phenomenology of melancholia, mania, and schizophrenia, Part II. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 20(7–8), 131–152.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sass, L. A., & Pienkos, E. (2013c). Delusions: The phenomenological approach. In W. Fulford, M. Davies, G. Graham, J. Sadler, & G. Stanghellini (Eds.), Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Psychiatry (pp. 632–657). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sass, L. A., Parnas, J., & Zahavi, D. (2011). Phenomenological psychopathology and schizophrenia: contemporary approaches and misunderstandings. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology, 18(1), 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sass, L. A., Pienkos, E., & Nelson, B. (2013). Introspection and schizophrenia: a comparative investigation of anomalous self experiences. Consciousness and Cognition, 22, 430–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scarry, E. (1985). The body in pain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, S. (1982). Is there a schizophrenic language? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 5, 579–588.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shenk, J. W. (2002). A melancholy of mine own. In M. Casey (Ed.), Unholy ghost: Writers on depression (pp. 242–255). New York: Harper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shorter, E. (2013). How everyone became depressed: The rise and fall of the nervous breakdown. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silber, E., Rey, A. C., Savard, R., & Post, R. M. (1980). Thought disorder and affective inaccessibility in depression. Journal of Clinical Psychiatry, 41(5), 161–165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J. (1999). Where the roots reach for water. New York: North Point Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Society for the Advancement of General Systems Theory (1962). General Systems, (pp. 7–8).

  • Sontag, S. (Ed.). (1976). Antonin Artaud: Selected writings. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

  • Spitzer, M. (1997). A cognitive neuroscience of schizophrenic thought disorder. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 23(1), 29–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanghellini, G., & Ballerini, M. (2004). Autism: disembodied experience. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology, 11(3), 259–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanghellini, G., & Ballerini, M. (2007). Values in persons with schizophrenia. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 33, 131–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Styron, W. (1990). Darkness visible. New York: Modern Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tatossian, A. (1997). La phenomenologie des psychoses. Paris: L’Art du Comprendre.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, M. A. (1992). Are schizophrenia and affective disorders related? A selective literature review. The American Journal of Psychiatry, 149(1), 22–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trichard, C., Martinot, J. L., Alagille, M., Masure, M. C., Hardy, P., Ginstet, D., et al. (1995). Time course of prefrontal lobe dysfunction in severely depressed in-patients: a longitudinal neuropsychological study. Psychological Medicine, 25(1), 79–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trow, G. (1997). Within the context of no context. New York: Atlantic Monthly.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsuang, M. T., & Simpson, J. C. (1984). Schizoaffective disorder: concept and reality. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 10(1), 14–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Os, J. (2009). A salience dysregulation syndrome. British Journal of Psychiatry, 194, 101–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Os, J. (2012). Introduction: the extended psychosis phenotype-relationships with schizophrenia and with ultrahigh risk status for psychosis. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 38(2), 227–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (1904/1949). Objectivity in social science and social policy. In E. A. Shills, & H. A. Finch (Eds.), The Methodology of the Social Sciences. New York: Free Press.

  • Wiggins, O. P., & Schwartz, M. A. (1991). Research into personality disorders: the alternatives of dimensions and ideal types. Journal of Personality Disorders, 5(1), 69–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1922). Tractatus logico-philosophicus. New York: Harcourt, Brace and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1958). Philosophical investigations. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolfson, L. (1970). Le schizo et les langues. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods, A. (2011). The limits of narrative: provocations for the medical humanities. Medical Humanities, 37, 73–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wykes, T., & Leff, J. (1982). Disordered speech: differences between manics and schizophrenics. Brain and Language, 15, 117–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Louis Sass.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Sass, L., Pienkos, E. Beyond words: linguistic experience in melancholia, mania, and schizophrenia. Phenom Cogn Sci 14, 475–495 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-013-9340-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-013-9340-0

Keywords

Navigation