Skip to main content
Log in

Fairness Between Competing Claims

  • Published:
Res Publica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Fairness is a central, but under-theorized, notion in moral and political philosophy. This paper makes two contributions. Firstly, it criticizes Broome’s seminal account of fairness in (1990–1991) Proc Aristotelian Soc 91:87–101, showing that there are problems with restricting fairness to a matter of relative satisfaction and holding that it does not itself require the satisfaction of the claims in question. Secondly, it considers the justification of lotteries to resolve cases of ties between competing claims, which Broome claims as support for his theory, and contrasts random procedures to contests of skill, which may also be considered lotteries in a broader sense. I offer no alternative account of fairness of my own, but hope to point the way for future research on the nature of fairness.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This has led some to question the importance of the distinction (e.g. see Sen 2009, pp. 72–74). Translators have been forced to adopt various renderings of ‘justice as fairness’—for instance in Spanish it becomes ‘justicia como equidad’ and in Italian ‘giustizia come equità’ (both closer to ‘equity’), while in Swedish it is ‘rättvisa som skälighet’ (with connotations of reasonableness). I thank Yolanda Cuevas, Isabelle Deganis, Murial Kahane, Rasmus Karlsson, Hugh Lazenby, Miriam Ronzoni, and Christian Schemmel for their linguistic expertise.

  2. Compare Stone (2009), p. 398 who insists it is more just to satisfy claims.

  3. I am assuming, as Broome seems to, that the strength of the claim is simply dependent upon the amount of money owed. Matters would be more complicated if one party could have a very strong claim to the £10 that you owed them, while the other had a weaker claim to £20. Then the extent to which each should be satisfied would presumably be a function of the strength of their claim multiplied by what it is a claim to.

  4. I assume it would still be fair if I was to pay them £40 and £20, respectively, thereby giving each twice what they had a claim to, though Broome is not explicit on this point. If we were dividing business profits proportionately to initial investment, this is what we would do, though if I am merely giving my friends a gift on top of repaying what I owe then perhaps I should give each an equal amount extra.

  5. This problem is avoided by the account of Stone (2009), p. 398, which requires only that ‘strong claims are to be satisfied before weak claims,’ though this does not seem to permit all the lotteries that Broome would (specifically, ones where a slightly weaker claim-bearer may nonetheless get the good rather than having her claim ignored).

  6. I prefer the locution ‘claim-bearers’ to Broome’s ‘claimants.’ Claim-bearer implies that the parties do in fact have claims to the good. A claimant may be someone who merely claims the good, though he has no claim to it (though this is surely not Broome’s intended meaning).

  7. Of these rivals, Greely (1977) primarily concerns the constitutionality of lotteries and avoiding improper biases in allocation. Sher (1980) is primarily concerned with what makes a lottery a fair one rather than an unfair one, but suggests lotteries can be used to ensure that no one can allocate a good simply as he wishes. Kornhauser and Sager (1988) justify lotteries only when competing claims are exactly equal.

  8. Stone (2008), pp. 576–580 attributes the necessity of actual consent to Sher (1980). This is not obviously the best way to read Sher’s paper. It is not clear that Sher (1980), pp. 212–214 is intended to allow parties to veto any distributive procedure; perhaps they can only veto a procedure that favours some claim-bearer. If so, they cannot veto a fair coin-toss.

  9. In practice, most luck egalitarians are pluralists, so may admit that all things considered one ought to prefer a Pareto superior outcome, even if unfair.

  10. Defences of lotteries that emphasize the importance of publicity (e.g. Stone 2009; Saunders 2010a) are really concerned with the latter notion.

  11. At least, this is commonly accepted, though it has recently been disputed by Brighouse and Fleurbaey (forthcoming).

  12. Where they test an irrelevant attribute, they may be fair insofar as they are lotteries; but since they involve uncertainty rather than risk they are generally less desirable than random devices (Stone 2008, pp. 585–587).

References

  • Beitz, Charles. 1989. Political equality: An essay in democratic theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brighouse, Harry and Marc Fleurbaey. Democracy and proportionality. The Journal of Political Philosophy (forthcoming). doi: 1111/j.1467-9760.2008.00316.x.

  • Broome, John. 1998. Kamm on fairness. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58: 955–961.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broome, John. 1990–1991. Fairness. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 91: 87–101.

  • Christiano, Thomas. 2009. Debate: Estlund on democratic authority. The Journal of Political Philosophy 17: 228–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christiano, Thomas, and Will Braynen. 2008. Inequality, injustice and levelling down. Ratio 21: 392–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, Gerald. 1989. On the currency of egalitarian justice. Ethics 99: 906–944.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, Gerald. 2008. Rescuing justice and equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald. 2000. Sovereign virtue: The theory and practice of equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Estlund, David. 2008. Democratic authority: A philosophical framework. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greely, Hank. 1977. The equality of allocation by lot. Harvard Civil Rights-Civil Liberties Law Review 12: 113–141.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hooker, Brad. 2005. Fairness. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 8: 329–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kornhauser, Lewis, and Lawrence Sager. 1988. Just lotteries. Social Science Information 27: 483–516.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mason, Andrew. 2001. Egalitarianism and the levelling down objection. Analysis 61: 246–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norman, Richard. 2001. Criteria of justice: Desert, needs and equality. Res Publica 7: 115–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, Derek. 1997. Equality and priority. Ratio 10: 202–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1999. A theory of justice, Revised edn. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, Nicholas. 2002. Fairness: Theory & practice of distributive justice. London: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radcliffe Richards, Janet. 1997. Equality of opportunity. Ratio 10: 253–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saunders, Ben. 2008. The equality of lotteries. Philosophy 83: 359–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saunders, Ben. 2009. A defence of weighted lotteries in life saving cases. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 12: 279–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saunders, Ben. 2010a. Sex discrimination, gender balance, justice and publicity in admissions. Journal of Applied Philosophy 27: 59–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saunders, Ben. 2010b. Why majority rule cannot be based only on procedural equality. Ratio Juris 23: 113–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saunders, Ben. 2010c. Estlund’s flight from fairness. Representation 46: 5–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saunders, Ben. 2010d. “It’s a lottery!”: Penalties and the meaning of winning. In Soccer and Philosophy, ed. Ted Richards, 335–345. Open Court: Chicago and L Salle, Illinois.

  • Scanlon, Thomas. 1975. Preference and urgency. Journal of Philosophy 72: 655–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, Thomas. 1998. What we owe to each other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler, Samuel. 2003. What is egalitarianism? Philosophy & Public Affairs 31: 5–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, Amartya. 2009. The idea of justice. London: Allen Lane.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sher, George. 1980. What makes a lottery fair? Noûs 14: 203–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stone, Peter. 2007. Why lotteries are just. The Journal of Political Philosophy 15: 276–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stone, Peter. 2008. On fair lotteries. Social Theory and Practice 34: 573–590.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stone, Peter. 2009. Lotteries, justice and probability. Journal of Theoretical Politics 21: 395–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walzer, Michael. 1983. Spheres of justice: A defence of pluralism and equality. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Bernard. 1973. The idea of equality. In Problems of the self: Collected papers 1956-72. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Wolff, Jonathan. 1998. Fairness, respect, and the egalitarian ethos. Philosophy & Public Affairs 27: 207–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

In addition to those in footnote 1; I thank John Broome and two anonymous referees for helpful comments on an earlier version of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ben Saunders.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Saunders, B. Fairness Between Competing Claims. Res Publica 16, 41–55 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-010-9118-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-010-9118-y

Keywords

Navigation