Skip to main content
Log in

Conscious Will, Reason-Responsiveness, and Moral Responsibility

  • Published:
The Journal of Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Empirical evidence challenges many of the assumptions that underlie traditional philosophical and commonsense conceptions of human agency. It has been suggested that this evidence threatens also to undermine free will and moral responsibility. In this paper, I will focus on the purported threat to moral responsibility. The evidence challenges assumptions concerning the ability to exercise conscious control and to act for reasons. This raises an apparent challenge to moral responsibility as these abilities appear to be necessary for morally responsible agency. I will argue that this challenge collapses once the underlying conditions on moral responsibility are specified in sufficient detail. I will argue, in other words, that the empirical evidence does not support a challenge to the assumption that we are, in general, morally responsible agents. In the final section, I will suggest that empirical research on human agency is nevertheless relevant to various questions about moral responsibility.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Obviously, EC1 and EC2 are closely related and there is a potential overlap as the conscious control of action can plausibly be taken to involve the conscious initiation of action. Nevertheless, the two claims can be distinguished from each other insofar as they are based on distinct strands of empirical research.

  2. The empirical challenge to moral responsibility has received much attention, but not much detailed analysis. It has usually been addressed by way of addressing the challenge to free will, and the two challenges have often not been clearly distinguished. See Libet (1999); Wegner (2002); Greene and Cohen (2004); Roskies (2006); and many of the contributions to Pockett et al. (2006); Baer et al. (2008); Sinnott-Armstrong and Nadel (2011). Doris (2002) and Nelkin (2005) focus on the challenge to moral responsibility, but their discussion is restricted to the challenge from EC4.

  3. Cases that involve severe addiction are more complicated, but we can ignore this issue here.

  4. Note the difference between this case and cases of indirect (or derived) responsibility, such as drunk driving. Indirect responsibility is grounded in earlier acts for which one is directly responsible. This cannot be said about the present case, for it is not clear that the omission of not indicating a lane change can be traced back to earlier acts. We assume that you have a habit of not indicating, but you may not have done anything to acquire this habit.

  5. I shall assume here for the sake of argument that the conscious events that proximately preceded the movements were conscious intentions. I should note, however, that this assumption has also been questioned. For instance, Keller and Heckhausen (1990, 359) suggested that the conscious events in question were the result of the “selective attention” to look for an urge to move, which was, in turn, induced by the artificial setup and the instructions of the experiment. They suggested, in other words, that the conscious events in question were neither intentions nor conscious events that precede ordinary actions.

  6. Libet and his followers assumed such a strong conception of free will (Libet 1999; Wegner 2002). Some philosophers think that free choices can be conditioned by antecedent states and events only if the conditioning is not deterministic (Kane 1998; O’Connor 2000; Pereboom 2001; Clarke 2003). Others, including myself, think that free will is compatible with deterministic causation as well. In any case, the point here is merely that it seems at least prima facie plausible to require unconditioned control for free will.

  7. Elsewhere I have responded to the closely related neuroscientific challenge to free will and to Daniel Wegner’s empirical argument for the claim that conscious will is an illusion. See Schlosser (2012a, b).

  8. According to Fischer and Ravizza (1998), reason-responsiveness can be analyzed in terms of counterfactual conditionals. I am sympathetic to this view, but here I presume only the weaker claim that the truth of certain counterfactuals counts as evidence for reason-responsiveness.

  9. Note that it would not seem to be particularly difficult to gather this kind of evidence. With respect to the position effect, for instance, it would be interesting to see what happens in cases where there are clear qualitative differences. This would provide a contrast class that may tell us something interesting about our responsiveness to the relevant reasons.

  10. As Nelkin (2005) points out, the challenge here does not stem from the thesis of situationism (EC4) itself, but from the empirical evidence for this view.

  11. As pointed out in Sect. 5, ACC appears to be the best candidate for establishing a plausible connection between moral responsibility and conscious control. Should ACC be untenable, then so are the empirical challenges to moral responsibility from conscious control.

  12. I am setting aside here the difficult question of whether imprisonment and other forms of legal punishment are effective means for the regulation of behavior and society—this is a separate issue.

  13. According to Fischer and Ravizza (1998), reason-responsiveness requires that there is an understandable pattern of counterfactual scenarios in which the agent recognizes the relevant reason and that there is at least one possible world in which the agent acts on that recognition (69–81). This account would seem to support my claim that the degree of reason-responsiveness is sufficiently robust in the cases in question.

References

  • American Law Institute. 1985. Model penal code and commentaries. Philadelphia, PA: The American Law Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arpaly, Nomy. 2003. Unprincipled virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baer, John, James C. Kaufman, and Roy F. Baumeister (eds.). 2008. Are we free? Psychology and free will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bandura, Albert. 1999. Moral disengagement in the perpetration of inhumanities. Personality and Social Psychology Review 3: 193–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bargh, John A., and Tanya L. Chartrand. 1999. The unbearable automaticity of being. American Psychologist 54: 462–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumeister, Roy F., E.J. Masicampo, and Kathleen D. Vohs. 2011. Do conscious thoughts cause behavior? Annual Review of Psychology 62: 331–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blair, Irene V. 2002. The malleability of automatic stereotypes and prejudice. Personality and Social Psychology Review 6: 242–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, Michael E. 2004. Planning agency, autonomous agency. In Personal autonomy, ed. James Stacey Taylor, 33–57. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burns, Kelly, and Antoine Bechara. 2007. Decision making and free will: A neuroscience perspective. Behavioral Sciences and the Law 25: 263–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burns, Jeffrey M., and Russell H. Swerdlow. 2003. Right orbitofrontal tumor with pedophilia symptom and constructional apraxia sign. Archives of Neurology 60: 437–440.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carlson, Michael, Ventura Charlin, and Norman. Miller. 1988. Positive mood and helping behavior: A test of six hypotheses. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 55: 211–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, Randolph. 2003. Libertarian accounts of free will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Custers, Ruud, and Henk Aarts. 2010. The unconscious will: How the pursuit of goals operates outside of conscious awareness. Science 329: 47–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Donald. 1963. Actions, reasons, and causes. Journal of Philosophy 60: 685–700.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Neys, Wim. 2006. Dual processing in reasoning: Two systems but one reasoner. Psychological Science 17: 428–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, Daniel C. 1984. Elbow room: The varieties of free will worth wanting. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devine, Patricia G., E. Ashby Plant, David M. Amodio, E. Eddie Harmon-Jones, and Stephanie L. Vance. 2002. The regulation of explicit and implicit race bias: The role of motivations to respond without prejudice. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 82: 835–848.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dijksterhuis, Ap. 2004. Think different: The merits of unconscious thought in preference development and decision making. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 87: 586–598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doris, John M. 2002. Lack of character: Personality and moral behavior. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Gerald. 1988. The theory and practice of autonomy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, Jonathan St.B.T. 2008. Dual-processing accounts of reasoning, judgment, and social cognition. Annual Review of Psychology 59: 255–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, John M. 1994. The metaphysics of free will. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, John M. 2012. Semicompatibilism and its rivals. Journal of Ethics 16: 117–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, John M., and Mark Ravizza. 1998. Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, Harry G. 1969. Alternate possibilities and moral responsibility. Journal of Philosophy 66: 829–839.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, Harry G. 1971. Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. Journal of Philosophy 68: 5–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gazzaniga, Michael S., and Joseph E. LeDoux. 1978. The integrated mind. New York: Plenum.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, Alvin. 1970. A theory of human action. New York: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gollwitzer, Peter M., and Paschal Sheeran. 2006. Implementation intentions and goal achievement: A meta-analysis of effects and processes. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology 38: 69–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, Joshua, and Jonathan Cohen. 2004. For the law, neuroscience changes nothing and everything. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B 359: 1775–1785.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenwald, Anthony G., and Mahzarin R. Banaji. 1995. Implicit social cognition: Attitudes, self-esteem, and stereotypes. Psychological Review 102: 4–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenwald, Anthony G., and Linda H. Krieger. 2006. Implicit bias: Scientific foundations. California Law Review 94: 945–967.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haney, Craig, Curtis Banks, and Philip Zimbardo. 1973. Study of prisoners and guards in a simulated prison. Naval Research Reviews 9: 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, Gilbert. 1999. Moral philosophy meets social psychology: Virtue ethics and the fundamental attribution error. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 99: 315–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, David. 1960. A treatise of human nature, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge. Oxford: Clarendon Press (originally published 1740).

  • Johansson, Petter, Lars Hall, Sverker Sikström, Betty Tärning, and Andreas Lind. 2006. How something can be said about telling more than we can know: On choice blindness and introspection. Consciousness and Cognition 15: 673–692.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jolls, Christine, and Cass R. Sunstein. 2006. The Law of implicit bias. California Law Review 94: 969–996.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kane, Robert. 1998. The significance of free will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller, I., and H. Heckhausen. 1990. Readiness potentials preceding spontaneous motor acts: Voluntary vs. involuntary control. Electroencephalography and Clinical Neurophysiology 76: 351–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keren, Gideon, and Yaacov Schul. 2009. Two is not always better than one: A critical evaluation of two-system theories. Perspectives on Psychological Science 4: 533–550.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kihlstrom, John F. 1987. The cognitive unconscious. Science 237: 1445–1452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Libet, Benjamin. 1985. Unconscious cerebral initiative and the role of conscious will in voluntary action. Behavioral and Brain Science 8: 529–566.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Libet, Benjamin. 1999. Do we have free will? Journal of Consciousness Studies 6: 47–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, Alfred. 1995. Autonomous agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, Alfred. 2003. Motivation and agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, Alfred. 2009. Efficacious intentions: The power of conscious will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milgram, Stanley. 1963. Behavioral study of obedience. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 67: 371–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milgram, Stanley. 1974. Obedience to authority: An experimental view. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, Christian. 2009. Social psychology, mood, and helping: Mixed results for virtue ethics. Journal of Ethics 13: 145–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morse, Stephen J. 2006. Moral and legal responsibility and the new neuroscience. In Neuroethics, ed. Judy Illes, 33–50. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelkin, Dana K. 2005. Freedom, responsibility and the challenge of situationism. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 29: 181–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelkin, Dana K. 2011. Making sense of freedom and responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nisbett, Richard E., and Timothy D. Wilson. 1977. Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological Review 84: 231–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, Timothy. 2000. Persons and causes: The metaphysics of free will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Osman, Magda. 2004. An evaluation of dual-process theories of reasoning. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review 11: 988–1010.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, Derk. 2001. Living without free will. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pockett, Susan, William P. Banks, and Shaun Gallagher (eds.). 2006. Does consciousness cause behavior?. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roskies, Adina. 2006. Neuroscientific challenges to free will and responsibility. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 10: 419–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, Lee, and Richard E. Nisbett. 1991. The person and the situation. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T.M. 1986. The significance of choice. The Tanner Lectures on Human Values 7: 149–216.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T.M. 1998. What we owe to each other. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlick, Moritz. 1939. When is a man responsible? In Problems of ethics, ed. Moritz Schlick, 141–158. New York: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlosser, Markus E. 2010. Agency, ownership, and the standard theory. In New waves in philosophy of action, ed. Jesus Aguilar, Andrei A. Buckareff, and Keith Frankish, 13–31. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlosser, Markus E. 2012a. Free will and the unconscious precursors of choice. Philosophical Psychology 25: 365–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlosser, Markus E. 2012b. Causally efficacious intentions and the sense of agency: In defense of real mental causation. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 32: 135–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter, and Lynn Nadel (eds.). 2011. Conscious will and responsibility: A tribute to Benjamin Libet. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sloman, Steven A. 1996. The empirical case for two systems of reasoning. Psychological Bulletin 119: 3–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smart, J.J.C. 1961. Free will, praise, and blame. Mind 70: 291–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Angela M. 2005. Responsibility for attitudes: Activity and passivity in mental life. Ethics 115: 236–271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soon, Chun Siong, Marcel Brass, Hans-Jochen Heinze, and John-Dylan Haynes. 2008. Unconscious determinants of free decisions in the human brain. Nature Neuroscience 11: 543–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, Peter F. 1962. Freedom and resentment. Proceedings of the British Academy 48: 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, Peter. 1983. An essay on free will. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vargas, Manuel. 2007. Revisionism. In Four views on free will, ed. John M. Fischer, Robert Kane, Derk Pereboom, and Manuel Vargas, 126–165. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, R.Jay. 1994. Responsibility and the moral sentiments. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson, Gary. 1975. Free agency. Journal of Philosophy 72: 205–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Webb, Thomas L., and Paschal Sheeran. 2006. Does changing behavioral intentions engender behavior change? A meta-analysis of the experimental evidence. Psychological Bulletin 132: 249–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, Daniel M. 2002. The illusion of conscious will. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, Susan. 1990. Freedom within reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhu, Jing. 2003. Reclaiming volition: An alternative interpretation of Libet’s experiment. Journal of Consciousness Studies 10: 61–77.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The research for this article was funded by a grant from the Netherlands Organization for Scientific Research (NWO). Earlier versions were presented at the 38th Conference on Value Inquiry (Salem State University), a workshop on Responsibility and Neuroscience (Institute of Philosophy, London), and a research meeting at the University of Leiden. I would like to thank the participants at these meetings for their helpful comments, and I am especially grateful to Neil Levy for very helpful written comments on an earlier draft.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Markus E. Schlosser.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Schlosser, M.E. Conscious Will, Reason-Responsiveness, and Moral Responsibility. J Ethics 17, 205–232 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-013-9143-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-013-9143-0

Keywords

Navigation