Skip to main content
Log in

Evidential bilattice logic and lexical inference

  • Published:
Journal of Logic, Language and Information Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper presents an information-based logic that is applied to the analysis of entailment, implicature and presupposition in natural language. The logic is very fine-grained and is able to make distinctions that are outside the scope of classical logic. It is independently motivated by certain properties of natural human reasoning, namely partiality, paraconsistency, relevance, and defeasibility: once these are accounted for, the data on implicature and presupposition comes quite naturally.

The logic is based on the family of semantic spaces known as bilattices, originally proposed by Ginsberg (1988), and used extensively by Fitting (1989, 1992). Specifically, the logic is based on a subset of bilattices that I call evidential bilattices, constructed as the Cartesian product of certain algebras with themselves. The specific details of the epistemic agent approach of the logical system is derived from the work of Belnap (1975, 1977), augmented by the use of evidential links for inferencing. An important property of the system is that it has been implemented using an extension of Fitting's work on bilattice logic programming (1989, 1991) to build a model-based inference engine for the augmented Belnap logic. This theorem prover is very efficient for a reasonably wide range of inferences.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • AndersonA. and BelnapN., 1975, Entailment: The Logic of Relevance and Necessity, I. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • AvronA., 1992, “Whither relevance logic?,” Journal of Philosophical Logic 21, 243–281.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barba EscribaJ., 1992, “Two formal systems for situation semantics,” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 33(1), 70–88.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J., 1989, “Situations and small worlds,” pp. 79–92 in The Situation in Logic, Center for the Study of Language and Information.

  • BarwiseJ. and SeligmanJ., 1994. “The rights and wrongs of natural regularity,” in: Philosophical Perspectives, pp. 331–364 J.Tomberlin, ed. California: Ridgeview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beaver, D., 1993, “What comes first in dynamic semantics,” Research Report LP-93-15, Institute for Logic, Language and Computation, University of Amsterdam.

  • BelnapN., 1975. “How a computer should think,” pp. 30–56, in Contemporary Aspects of Philosophy, G.Ryle, ed., Stocksfield: Oriel Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • BelnapN., 1977. “A useful four-valued logic,” pp. 8–37 in Modern Uses of Multiple-Valued Logic, J.Dunn and G.Epstein, eds., Vol. 2 of Episteme, Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • BlameyS., 1986, “Partial logic,” pp. 1–70 iin Handbook of Philosophical Logic, Vol. III, D.Gabbay and F.Guenthner, eds., Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burton-Roberts, N., 1989, The Limits to Debate: A Revised Theory of Semantic Presupposition, Vol. 51 of Cambridge Studies in Linguistics, Cambridge University Press.

  • CrossC. and ThomasonR., 1992. “Conditionals and knowledge-base update,” pp. 247–275 in, Belief Revision, P.Gädenfors, ed., Chapter 10, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • deKleerJ., 1986, “An assumption-based TMS,” Artificial Intelligence 28, 127–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • DevlinK., 1991, Information and Logic, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • DowtyD., WallR., and PetersS., 1981, Introduction to Montague Semantics. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • FauconnierG., 1985, Mental Spaces: Aspects of Meaning Construction in Natural Language. Cambridge, Mass.: Bradford Books, The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitting, M., 1989, “Negation as refutation,” pp. 63–70 in Proceedings of the Fourth Annual Symposium on Logic in Computer Science, R. Parikh, ed., IEEE.

  • Fitting, M., 1990, “Kleene's three-valued logics and their children,” in Proceedings of the Bulgarian Kleene '90 Conference, (unpublished ms.).

  • FittingM., 1991, “Bilattices and the semantics of logic programming,” Journal of Logic Programming 11, 91–116.

    Google Scholar 

  • FittingM., 1992, “Kleene's logic, generalized,” Journal of Logic and Computation 1, 797–810.

    Google Scholar 

  • GazdarG., 1979. Pragmatics: Implicature, Presupposition and Logical Form. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • GinsbergM., 1988, “Multivalued logics: A uniform approach to reasoning in artificial intelligence,” Computational Intelligence 4, 265–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • GriceP., 1975, “Logic and conversation,” in Syntax and Semantics, Volume 3: Speech Acts, P.Cole and J.L.Morgan, eds., New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • GroenendijkJ. and StokhofM., 1991, “Dynamic predicate logic,” Linguistics and Philosophy 14, 39–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gunji, T., 1982, Towards a Computational Theory of Pragmatics: Discourse, Presupposition and Implicature, Indiana University Linguistics Club.

  • KarttunenL. and PetersS., 1979, “Conventional implicature,” in Syntax and Semantics, Volume 11: Presupposition, C.-H.Oh and D.Dinneen, eds., New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kempson, R., 1975, Presupposition and the Delimitation of Semantics, Cambridge University Press.

  • KleeneS., 1952, Introduction to Metamathematics, Vol. 1 of Bibliotheca Mathematica, Groningen: North-Holland Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Konolige, K., 1988, “Hierachical autoepistemic theories for nonmonotonic reasoning: Preliminary report,” Technical Note 446, Artifical Intelligence Center, Center for the Study of Language and Information, Computer and Information Sciences Division.

  • Makinson, D., 1989, “General theory of cumulative inference,” pp. 1–128 in, Second International Workshop on Non-Monotonic Reasoning. Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence 346, R. Parikh, ed.

  • Mercer, R., 1992a, “A default logic approach to the derivation of natural language presupposition,’ Technical Report 332, Department of Computer Science, The University of Western Ontario.

  • MercerR., 1992b, “Default logic: Towards a common logical semantics for presuppositions and entailments,” Journal of Semantics 9, 223–250.

    Google Scholar 

  • Muskens, R., 1988, “Going partial in Montague Grammar,” Technical Report 0, Institute for Languag, Logic and Information.

  • PriestG., 1979, “The logic of paradox,” Journal of Philosophical Logic 8, 219–241.

    Google Scholar 

  • PriestG. and RoutleyR., 1989a, “The philosophical significance and inevitability of paraconsistency,” in Paraconsistent Logic: Essays on the Inconsistent, G.Priest, R.Routley, and J.Norman, eds., München: Philosophia Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • PriestG. and RoutleyR., 1989b, “Systems of paraconsistent logic,” in Paraconsistent Logic: Essays on the Inconsistent, G.Priest, R.Routley, and J.Norman, eds., München: Philosophia Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • ReadS., 1988, Relevant Logic: A Philosophical Examination of Inference, Oxford: Basil Blackwell Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • ReiterR., 1987, “A logic for default reasoning,” pp. 69–83 in Readings in Nonmonotonic Reasoning, M.Ginsberg, ed., Chapter 3.1, Los Altos, CA: Morgan Kaufmann.

    Google Scholar 

  • RescherN., 1969, Many-Valued Logic, New York: McGraw-Hill Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schöter, A., 1995, “Paraconsistent feature logic,” in Nonclassical Feature Systems, A. Schöter and C. Vogel, eds., Edinburgh Working Papers in Cognitive Science, Volume 10, Chapter 1, Centre for Cognitive Science, The University of Edinburgh.

  • ThijsseE., 1990, “Partial logic and modal logic: a systematic survey,” Research Report ITK 11, Institute for Language Technology and Artificial Intelligence, Tilburg University, The Netherlands.

    Google Scholar 

  • Veltman, F., 1991, “Defaults in update semantics,” DYANA Deliverable R2.5.C, ILLC/Department of Philosophy, University of Amsterdam.

  • WilkesA. and LeatherbarrowM., 1988, “Editing episodic memory following the identification of error,” The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology 40A(2), 361–387.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Additional information

A shorter version of this material was originally presented at the Fifth International Symposium on Logic and Language, Noszvaj, Hungary, 1994. The author is now in the Mathematical Reasoning Group, Department of Artificial Intelligence, University of Edinburgh, 80 South Bridge, Edinburgh EH1 1HN, U.K.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Schöter, A. Evidential bilattice logic and lexical inference. J Logic Lang Inf 5, 65–105 (1996). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00215627

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00215627

Key words

Navigation