Skip to main content
Log in

Reduction: the Cheshire cat problem and a return to roots

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I propose two theses, and then examine what the consequences of those theses are for discussions of reduction and emergence. The first thesis is that what have traditionally been seen as robust, reductions of one theory or one branch of science by another more fundamental one are a largely a myth. Although there are such reductions in the physical sciences, they are quite rare, and depend on special requirements. In the biological sciences, these prima facie sweeping reductions fade away, like the body of the famous Cheshire cat, leaving only a smile. ... The second thesis is that the “smiles” are fragmentary patchy explanations, and though patchy and fragmentary, they are very important, potentially Nobel-prize winning advances. To get the best grasp of these “smiles,” I want to argue that, we need to return to the roots of discussions and analyses of scientific explanation more generally, and not focus mainly on reduction models, though three conditions based on earlier reduction models are retained in the present analysis. I briefly review the scientific explanation literature as it relates to reduction, and then offer my account of explanation. The account of scientific explanation I present is one I have discussed before, but in this paper I try to simplify it, and characterize it as involving field elements (FE) and a preferred causal model system (PCMS) abbreviated as FE and PCMS. In an important sense, this FE and PCMS analysis locates an “explanation” in a typical scientific research article. This FE and PCMS account is illustrated using a recent set of neurogenetic papers on two kinds of worm foraging behaviors: solitary and social feeding. One of the preferred model systems from a 2002 Nature article in this set is used to exemplify the FE and PCMS analysis, which is shown to have both reductive and nonreductive aspects. The paper closes with a brief discussion of how this FE and PCMS approach differs from and is congruent with Bickle’s “ruthless reductionism” and the recently revived mechanistic philosophy of science of Machamer, Darden, and Craver.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Bickle J. (2003). Philosophy and neuroscience: A ruthlessly reductive account. Dordrecht, Kluwer

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickle J. (2006a). Neuroscience. In: Borchert D.M.(eds) Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Farmington Hills, MI: Macmillan Reference USA. Volume 6, pp. 563–572

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. (2006b) Synthese(this volume).

  • Bogen J. (2004). Analyzing causality: The opposite of counterfactual is factual. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science. 18(1): 3–26

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bogen, J. (2005). Regularities and causality: Generalizations and causal explanations. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biology and Biomedical Science, 36. [H-H paper]

  • Cheung B.H., Arellano-Carbajal F., Rybicki I. et al. (2004). Soluble guanylate cyclases act in neurons exposed to the body fluid to promote C. Elegans aggregation behavior. Current Biology. 14(12): 1105–1111

    Google Scholar 

  • Coates J.C., de Bono M. (2002). Antagonistic pathways in neurons exposed to body fluid regulate social feeding in C. Elegans. Nature. 419(6910): 925–929

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooke-Deegan R. (1994). Gene Wars. New York, Norton

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver C.F. (2005). Beyond reduction: Mechanisms, multifield integration, and the unity of science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences. 36:373–396

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Culp S., Kitcher P. (1989). Theory structure and theory change in molecular biology. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. 40, 459–483

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darden L. (2005). Relations among fields: Mendelian, cytological and molecular mechanisms. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences. 36: 349–371

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darden L. (2006). Reasoning in biological discoveries: essays on mechanisms, interfield relations, and anomaly resolution. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Darden L., Maull N. (1977). Interfield theories. Philosophy of Science. 44, 43–64

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Bono M., Bargmann C.I. (1998). Natural variation in a neuropeptide Y receptor homolog modifies social behavior and food response in C. Elegans. Cell. 94(5): 679–689

    Google Scholar 

  • de Bono M., Tobin D.M., Davis M.W. et al. (2002). Social feeding in C. Elegans is induced by neurons that detect aversive stimuli. Nature., 419(6910): 899–903

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Bono M., Villu Maricq A. (2005). Neuronal substrates of complex behaviours in C. Elegans. Annual Review of Neuroscience. 28: 451–501

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend P. (1962). Explanation, reduction, and empiricism. In: Feigl H.M., Minnesota G.(eds). Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, Vol. 3, pp. 28–97

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere R. (1984). Understanding scientific reasoning (2nd ed.) New York, Holt Reinhart and Winston

    Google Scholar 

  • Glennan S. (1996). Mechanisms and the nature of causation. Erkenntis. 44, 49–71

    Google Scholar 

  • Gray J.M., Karow D.S., Lu H. et al. (2004). Oxygen sensation and social feeding mediated by a C. Elegans guanylate cyclase homologue. Nature. 430(6997): 317–322

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel C.G., Oppenheim P. (1948). Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science. 15, 135–175

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgkin A.L., Huxley A.F. (1952). A quantitative description of membrane current and its application to conduction and excitation in nerve. Journal of Physiology. 117, 500–544

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgkin J., Plasterk R.H., Waterston R.H. (1995). The nematode Caenorhabditis elegans and its genome. Science. Oct 20. 270(5235): 410–414

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull D.L. (1974). Philosophy of biological science. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacob F., Monod J. (1961). Genetic regulatory mechanisms in the synthesis of proteins. Journal of Molecular Biology. 3, 318–356

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kandel E.R., Schwartz J.H., Jessell T.M. (2000). Principles of neural science. New York, McGraw-Hill, Health Professions Division

    Google Scholar 

  • Kemeny J., Oppenheim P. (1956). On reduction. Philosophical Studies. 7, 6–17

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P., Salmon W.C. (1989). Scientific explanation. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn T.S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago, University of Chicago Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos I. (1970). Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In: Lakatos I., Musgrave A.(eds). Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, pp. 91–196

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan L. (1977). Progress and its problems: Toward a theory of scientific growth. Berkeley, University of California Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer P., Darden L., Craver C. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science. 67, 1–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E. (1982). The growth of biological thought: Diversity, evolution, and inheritance. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel E. (1961). The structure of science; Problems in the logic of scientific explanation. New York, Harcourt

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper K.R. (1959). The logic of scientific discovery. New York, Basic Books

    Google Scholar 

  • Potter, C. J. Luo, L. (2003) Food for thought: a receptor finds its ligand. Nature Neuroscience, 6 Nov, 1119

  • Railton, P. (1980). Explaining explanation. Ph.D. Dissertation, Princeton, Princeton University

  • Rankin C.H. (2002). From gene to identified neuron to behaviour in C. Elegans. Natural Review Genetics 3(8): 622–630

    Google Scholar 

  • Rogers C., Reale V., Kim K. (2003). Inhibition of C Elegans social feeding by fmrfamide-related peptide activation of Npr-1. Natural Neuroscience, 6(11): 1178–1185

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruse M. (1973). Philosophy of biology. London, Hutchinson

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner K.F. (1967). Approaches to reduction. Philosophy of Science 34, 137–147

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner K.F. (1969). Correspondence rules. Philosophy of Science 36, 280–290

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner K.F. (1972). Nineteenth century Aether theories. Oxford, Pergamon Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner K.F. (1974a). The peripherality of reductionism in the development of molecular biology. Journal of the History of Biology. 7, 111–139

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner K.F. (1974b). Logic of discovery and justification in regulatory genetics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science. 4, 349–385

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner K.F. (1977). Reduction, reductionism, values, and progress in the biomedical sciences. In: Colodny R.(eds). Logic, laws, and life. Pittsburgh, University of Pittsburgh Press, Vol. 6 pp. 143–171

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner K.F. (1980). Theory structure in the biomedical sciences. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 5, 57–97

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner K.F. (1993a). Discovery and explanation in biology and medicine. Chicago, University of Chicago Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner K.F. (1993b). Clinical trials and causation: Bayesian perspectives. Statistical Medicine. 12(15–16): 1477–1494 (discussion 1495–1499)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner, K.F. (1998a). Genes, behavior, and developmental emergentism: one process, indivisible?. Philosophy of Science. 65(June) 209–252

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner K.F. (1999). Complexity and research strategies in behavioral and psychiatric genetics. In: Ronald A., Carson R., Mark A., (eds). Behavioral genetics: The clash of culture and biology. Baltimore, Johns Hopkins University Press, pp. 61–88

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner K.F. (2000). Behavior at the organismal and molecular levels: the case of C. Elegans. Philosophy of Science, 67, S273–S278

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner K.F. (2001d). Nature and nurture. Current Opinion in Psychiatry, 14(September) 486–490

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner, K. F. (2002a). Neuroethics: reductionism, emergence, and decision-making capacities. In Neuroethics: Mapping the Field: Conference Proceedings, May 13–14, 2002. San Francisco, California: Steven Marcus, New York: Dana Press, p. 367.

  • Schaffner K.F. (2002b). Reductionism, complexity and molecular medicine: genetic chips and the ‘globalization’ of the genome. In: Hull M.H.V., Van Regenmortel D. (eds). Promises Limits of reductionism in the biomedical sciences. London, John Wylie, pp. 323–347

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schilpp P.A., Einstein E. (1949). Albert Einstein, Philosopher-scientist. Evanston, IL: Library of Living Philosophers

  • Shapere D. (1977). Scientific theories and their domain. In: Suppe F.(eds). The structure of scientific theories. Illinois university Press, Urbana, IL, pp. 518–565

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon H. (1981). The sciences of the artificial. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Sokolowski M.B. (2002). Neurobiology: social eating for stress. Nature. 419(6910): 893–894

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sommerfeld A. (1950a). Lectures on theoretical physics: Electrodynamics. New York, Academic Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Sommerfeld A. (1950b). Lectures on theoretical physics: Optics. New York, Academic Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K., Griffiths P.E. (1999). Sex and death: An introduction to philosophy of biology. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern C., Sherwood E.R. (1966). The Origin of genetics; a Mendel source book. San Francisco, W. H. Freeman

    Google Scholar 

  • Sulston J.E., Schierenberg E., White J.G., Thomson J.N. (1983). The embryonic cell lineage of the nematode Caenorhabditis Elegans. Developmental Biology. 100, 64–119

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sulston J.E., Horvitz H.R. (1977) Post-embryonic cell lineages of the nematode, Caenorhabditis elegans. Developmental Biology, Mar; 56 (1):110–156

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tabery J. (2004). Activities and interactions. Philosophy of Science 71, 1–15

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen B.C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford, New York, Clarendon Press, Oxford Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Regenmortel M., Hull D., (eds) (2002). Promises and limits of reductionism in the biomedical sciences. London, John Wylie Ltd

    Google Scholar 

  • Waters C.K. (1990). Why the antireductionist consensus would not survive the case of classical genetics. Proceedings of the Philosophy of Science Association 1, 125–139

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson J.D. (1987). Molecular biology of the gene. Menlo Park, CA: Benjamin/Cummings

    Google Scholar 

  • White J.G., Southgate E., Thomson J.N., Brenner S. (1986). The structure of the nervous system of the nematode Caenorhabditis elegans. Phil. Trans. Roy. Soc. London Ser B. 314, 1–340

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt W. (1976a). Reductionism, levels of organization, and the mind-body problem. In: Globus G.et al. (eds) Consciousness and the brain. New York, Plenum Press, pp. 205–267

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt W. (1976b). Reductive explanation: a functional account. In: Cohen R.S.et al. (eds) Proceedings of the 1974 Philosophy of Science Association. Dordrecht, Reidel, pp. 671–710

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood W. (eds) (1988). The Nematode: Caenorhabditis elegans. Cold Spring Harbor, Cold Spring Harbor Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. New York, Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kenneth F. Schaffner.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Schaffner, K.F. Reduction: the Cheshire cat problem and a return to roots. Synthese 151, 377–402 (2006). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-006-9031-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-006-9031-2

Keywords

Navigation