Skip to main content
Log in

Action, mindreading and embodied social cognition

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

One of the central insights of the embodied cognition (EC) movement is that cognition is closely tied to action. In this paper, I formulate an EC-inspired hypothesis concerning social cognition. In this domain, most think that our capacity to understand and interact with one another is best explained by appeal to some form of mindreading. I argue that prominent accounts of mindreading likely contain a significant lacuna. Evidence indicates that what I call an agent’s actional processes and states—her goals, needs, intentions, desires, and so on—likely play important roles in and for mindreading processes. If so, a full understanding of mindreading processes and their role in cognition more broadly will require an understanding of how actional mental processes interact with, influence, or take part in mindreading processes.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. While mindreading theorists have not reached consensus on the nature of the processes that undergird mindreading—some think the processes are simulatory, others think the processes involve the application of a certain kind of theory, and others go for a hybrid of simulation and theory—for the bulk of this paper, I will treat them singly.

  2. There are more radical versions of this spectatorial complaint. According to one recent strand of embodied social cognition research, paying close attention to interaction motivates a move away from considering individual minds as loci of sociocognitive explanation. De Jaegher et al. (2010), for example, draw a distinction between individualist and interactionist explanations, as follows. Individualist explanations rely entirely on individual factors such as neural mechanisms and allow social interaction “at most a contextual role” (2010, p. 441). Interactionist explanations, however, rely on interaction “playing an enabling or constitutive role” (2010, p. 441). De Jaegher, Di Paolo and Gallagher argue that we should pursue interactionist explanations. The claim here is that social cognition is not reducible to the machinations of individual minds, and thus that social cognition research should explore the ways that the dynamics of interactive processes between agents couple individuals in crucial ways. On this account, social interactions take on a life of their own, exhibiting properties not reducible to the properties of individual cognitive mechanisms. As such, cases of social interaction represent the constitution of “an autonomous self-sustaining organization in the domain of relational dynamics” (2010, p. 442), and deserve explanations appropriate to their level of organization. It is worth noting that though I focus on individualist explanations, nothing I say is inconsistent with the potential importance of interactionist explanations. Indeed, it seems to me that both individualist and interactionist explanations will have roles to play in a mature understanding of social cognition.

  3. Regarding demotion arguments, see Spaulding (2010). Suffice it to say that I regard mindreading as important enough to worry about the proper characterization of mindreading processes.

  4. My hypothesis bears some similarity to a claim made by proponents of an enactive account of social cognition. According to McGann and De Jaegher, for example, “There is no such thing as neutral or objective perception, only valued and perspectival interaction, structured by the goals of the agent and the contingencies contextualized within those valued actions” (2009, p. 425). I am unsure, however, whether my approach is compatible, more generally, with the enactive one. McGann and De Jaegher, for example, go on to develop their account in the direction of the antiindividualist line canvassed in footnote 2. Further, the enactive approach brings with it a suite of interrelated concepts (e.g., autonomy, sense-making, social skill, etc.) and views (e.g., on perception, the constitution of consciousness, naturalistic value, the nature of cognition, etc.) that complicate matters considerably. Given my specific (and relatively modest) aims in this paper, I can afford to leave consideration of such issues for another time.

  5. Of course, Carruthers does not argue explicitly against the idea I’m pressing. Rather, a spectatorial account of the mindreading system’s functioning is taken for granted. It remains to be seen whether the influence of agential considerations could be made to fit within extant accounts of mindreading like Carruthers’.

  6. Some Gibsonians argue that our perception of affordances is nonrepresentational—a claim taken by many to undermine the explanatory value of the notion of affordances. However, we need not be antirepresentationalist to find the notion of affordances useful. On this issue, see Scarantino (2003).

  7. Some proponents of an embodied social cognition criticize studies like these for studying agents in environments that are too static. The idea is that the importance of interaction for social cognition might be best seen when agents are interacting with real agents (see, e.g., De Jaegher et al. 2010). I agree that studying interaction with real agents might reveal interesting features that interaction with static representations—i.e., photographs—cannot (see, e.g., Shockley et al. 2009; Richardson et al. 2007). The extent to which such research problematizes the fruitfulness of mindreading approaches is an issue for future empirical and conceptual work to address. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for raising this issue.

References

  • Alicke, M. (2008). Blaming badly. Journal of Cognition and Culture, 8, 179–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alicke, M., & Rose, D. (2010). Culpable control of moral concepts? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33, 330–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou, L. (2009). Simulation, situated conceptualization, and prediction. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London: Biological Sciences, 364, 1281–1289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bekkering, H., & Neggers, S. F. W. (2002). Visual search is modulated by action intentions. Psychological Science, 13, 370–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bub, D. N., Masson, M. E. J., & Cree, G. S. (2008). Evocation of functional and volumetric gestural knowledge by objects and words. Cognition, 106, 27–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Calvo-Merino, B., Glaser, D. E., Grezes, J., Passingham, R. E., & Haggard, P. (2005). Action observation and acquired motor skills: and fMRI study with expert dancers. Cerebral Cortex, 15, 1243–1249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2006). The architecture of the mind. Clarendon, Oxford University Press.

  • Carruthers, P. (2009a). How we know our own minds: the relationship between mindreading and metacognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32, 121–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2009b). Mindreading underlies metacognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32, 164–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2010). Introspection: divided and partly eliminated. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 80, 76–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher, H., Di Paolo, E., & Gallagher, S. (2010). Does social interaction constitute social cognition? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 14(10), 441–447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeWall, C. N., Maner, J. K., & Rouby, D. A. (2009). Social exclusion and early-stage interpersonal perception: selective attention to signs of acceptance. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 96, 729–741.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2001). The practice of mind: theory, simulation, or primary interaction. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8(5–7), 83–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2004). Understanding interpersonal problems in autism: interaction theory as an alternative to theory of mind. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology, 11(3), 199–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2008). Inference or interaction: social cognition without precursors. Philosophical Explorations, 11(3), 163–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Hutto, D. (2008). Understanding others through primary interaction and narrative practice. In J. Zlatev, T. P. Racine, C. Sinha, & E. Itkonen (Eds.), The shared mind: Perspectives on intersubjectivity (pp. 17–38). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glenberg, A. M. (2010). Embodiment as a unifying perspective for psychology. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 1(4), 586–596.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glenberg, A. M., & Kaschak, M. P. (2002). Grounding language in action. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 9, 558–565.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. J. (2006). Simulating minds: The philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience of mindreading. Oxford University Press.

  • Goldman, A., & de Vignemont, F. (2009). Is social cognition embodied? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 13(4), 154–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hommel, B. (2004). Event files: feature binding in and across perception and action. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8(11), 494–500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D. (2004). The limits of spectatorial folk psychology. Mind & Language, 19(5), 548–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D. (2008). Folk psychological narratives: The sociocultural basis of understanding reasons. MIT Press.

  • Ickes, W., & Simpson, J. A. (1997). Managing empathic accuracy in close relationships. In W. Ickes (Ed.), Empathic accuracy (pp. 218–250). New York: Guilford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ickes, W., & Simpson, J. A. (2001). Motivational aspects of empathic accuracy. In G. J. O. Fletcher & M. Clark (Eds.), The Blackwell handbook of social psychology: Interpersonal processes (pp. 229–249). Blackwell Publishers.

  • Ickes, W., Simpson, J. A., & Minda Oriña, M. (2005). Empathic accuracy and inaccuracy in close relationships. In B. F. Malle & S. D. Hodges (Eds.), Other minds: How humans bridge the divide between self and others (pp. 310–333). New York: The Guilford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaschak, M. P., & Maner, J. K. (2009). Embodiment, evolution, and social cognition: an integrative framework. European Journal of Social Psychology, 39, 1236–1244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loula, F., Prasad, S., Harber, K., & Shiffrar, M. (2005). Recognizing people from their movement. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 31(1), 210–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malle, B. F. (2004). How the mind explain behavior: Folk explanations, meaning, and social interaction. MIT Press.

  • Maner, J. K., Kenrick, D. T., Neuberg, S. L., Vaughn Becker, D., Robertson, T. E., Hofer, B., et al. (2005). Functional projection: how fundamental social motives can bias interpersonal perception. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 88, 63–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maner, J. K., Galliot, M. T., Rouby, D. A., & Miller, S. L. (2007a). Can’t take my eyes off you: attentional adhesion to mates and rivals. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 93, 389–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maner, J. K., DeWall, C. N., Baumeister, R. F., & Schaller, M. (2007b). Does social exclusion motivate interpersonal reconnection? Resolving the “porcupine problem”. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 92, 42–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGann, M., & De Jaegher, H. (2009). Self-other contingencies: enacting social perception. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 8(4), 417–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2010). Action-oriented perception. European Journal of Philosophy. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0378.2010.00407.x.

  • O’Regan, J. K., & Noe, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24(5), 883–917.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliffe, M. (2007). From folk psychology to commonsense. In D. D. Hutto & M. Ratcliffe (Eds.), Folk psychology reassessed (pp. 223–243). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, M. J., Marsh, K. L., Isenhower, R. W., Goodman, J. R. L., & Schmidt, R. C. (2007). Rocking together: dynamics of intentional and unintentional interpersonal coordination. Human Movement Science, 26, 867–891.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., & Sinigaglia, C. (2010). The functional role of the parieto-frontal mirror circuit: interpretations and misinterpretations. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 11, 264–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rueschemeyer, S.-A., Lindemann, O., Van Elk, M., & Bekkering, H. (2009). Embodied cognition: the interplay between automatic resonance and selection-for-action mechanisms. European Journal of Social Psychology, 39, 1180–1187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Safran Foer, J. (2005). Extremely loud and incredibly close. Houghton Mifflin.

  • Scarantino, A. (2003). Affordances explained. Philosophy of Science, 70(5), 949–961.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schilbach, L. (2010). A second-person approach to other minds. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 11, 449–449.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schubert, T. W., & Semin, G. R. (2009). Embodiment as a unifying perspective for psychology. European Journal of Social Psychology, 39(7), 1135–1141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shanton, K., & Goldman, A. (2010). Simulation theory. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 1(4), 527–538.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shockley, K., Richardson, D. C., & Dale, R. (2009). Conversation and coordinative structures. Topics in Cognitive Science, 1, 305–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, J. A., Minda Oriña, M., & Ickes, W. (2003). When accuracy hurts, and when it helps: a test of the accuracy model in marital interactions. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 85(5), 881–893.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, L. B. (2005). Action alters shape categories. Cognitive Science, 29, 665–679.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spaulding, S. (2010). Embodied cognition and mindreading. Mind & Language, 25, 119–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, M. (2002). Six views of embodied cognition. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 9(4), 625–636.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zawidzki, T. (2008). The function of folk psychology: mind reading or mindshaping? Philosophical Explorations, 11(3), 193–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zwaan, R. A., & Taylor, L. J. (2006). Seeing, acting, understanding: motor resonance in language comprehension. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 135, 1–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author would like to thank Mike Kaschak and two anonymous reviewers for helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper, as well as members of the Mindreading Reading Group for helpful discussion on relevant issues.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joshua Shepherd.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Shepherd, J. Action, mindreading and embodied social cognition. Phenom Cogn Sci 11, 507–518 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-011-9241-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-011-9241-z

Keywords

Navigation