Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Business Ethics After Citizens United: A Contractualist Analysis

  • Published:
Journal of Business Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In Citizens United v. Federal Election Commission (2010), the US Supreme Court sharply curtailed the ability of the state to limit political speech by for-profit corporations. This new legal situation elevates the question of corporate political involvement: in what manner and to what extent is it ethical for for-profit corporations to participate in the political process in a liberal democratic society? Using Scanlon’s version of contractualism, I argue for a number of substantive and procedural constraints on the political activities of businesses. Central to this contractualist analysis is (1) an identification of the self-governance-based interests of individuals that are affected by corporate political activity and (2) a method for judging the various assignments of social rights, duties and roles according to how they collectively meet those interests. Together, these two features make this contractualist approach distinctive and allow it to generate substantive ethical results.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Despite longstanding disagreements within democratic society about this question, the “business and corporate social responsibility literature contains little discussion of the ethics of business efforts to influence public policy decisions.” (Weber 1997, 73) Although Weber made this observation some time ago, the business ethics literature has given relatively little attention to this question.

  2. Whelan contends that political CSR theorists are concerned both to “normatively prescribe, and positively describe and explain, the political duties and activities of corporations.” (711) My goals in this paper are purely normative.

  3. Adults with severe cognitive deficiencies that prevent them from conceiving of and planning for their lives do not qualify as rational self-governors. While they do have moral standing, they are not the primary subjects of a theory of liberal democratic society.

  4. “In order for the idea of justification to a being to make sense it must at least be the kind of thing that can be conscious.” (Scanlon 1998, 197).

  5. Werhane advances this view: “the rights of organizations such as corporations are derived from, dependent upon, and secondary to, individual rights". (60).

  6. This phrasing is due to Rawls (1971, pp. 26–27).

  7. See Scanlon (1998) for a more formal statement of the account: “According to contractualism, when we address our minds to a question of right and wrong, what we are trying to decide is…whether certain principles are ones that no one if suitably motivated, could reasonably reject.” (189) Shortly later, he states that “our thinking about right and wrong is structured by…the aim of finding principles that others, insofar as they too have this aim, could not reasonably reject.” (191).

  8. This understanding of contractualism draws from Rahul Kumar’s individual reasons restriction: “Principles in virtue of which an act is judged wrong are to be defended, on this view, by appeal to considerations that have to do with the importance for an individual of its being impermissible to relate to another in this way.” (1999, 281).

  9. See Donaldson and Dunfee (1999). Freeman (2006) also presents a social contract theory of business ethics with his Rawlsian articulation of Kantian stakeholder theory. Note that Freeman includes business organizations as parties to the social contract.

  10. The libertarian should be especially careful not to assume that stockholders want to maximize profits. As Gowri observes: “It is plausible that shareholders seek profits, but it is not necessarily the case that they seek them at the cost of altered social and political structures. For instance, when I invest in a chemical company, I plausibly only want the level of profits feasible within the constraints of current environmental safeguards. Chemical stockholders obviously would like to make money, but are not obviously willing to legalize currently illegal levels of pollution.” (Gowri 1844).

  11. See Buchanan (1985) for a review of arguments for and against capitalism.

  12. There are many other non-contractualist defenses of democracy. See Christiano (1996).

  13. Once the rights of individuals are defined and protected, the equal consideration of interests requires the principle of majority rule, except when doing so systematically disfavors the interests of some citizens. The idea here is that the principle of majority rule is a principle that cannot be reasonably rejected—unless it systematically discounts the interests of some. In that case, some modification of the principle of majority rule is in order. For a contractualist defense of the principle that the greater number is morally significant, see Kumar (2001).

  14. The quote is from Scalia’s dissent in Austin (1990). The majority found legal limits on corporate speech to be Constitutional.

  15. Unfortunately, the production of false and misleading information has been a corporate strategy that has migrated from tobacco companies seeking to obscure the well-founded fact that cigarette smoking causes lung cancer to other industries. For example, some energy companies have recently pursued a strategy to obscure the overwhelming scientific consensus regarding the existence of human-caused global warming. For a review of Exxon’s efforts to undermine evidence concerning global warming see Mufson (2007).

  16. My thinking here has been advanced by related concerns in Hussain (2012).

  17. It is conceivable—although hardly relevant in the present American social and political context—that corporations could be morally permitted to get around the spirit of laws governing their political activity. This would be the case if the laws prevented them from effectively representing the legitimate interests of their stakeholders or from presenting information that is necessary for citizens to make informed social and political decisions.

  18. I thank Rahul Kumar for helping me to recognize this kind of interest.

  19. I would venture—with some trepidation—that businesses could enter the political arena to support matters on which all reasonable citizens agree. This would mean that they could help support the liberal democratic order itself, without endorsing a contested understanding of that order. This might make sense when the liberal democratic order itself was under threat, or required the help of the business world to maintain the stability of that order. Such activity would, however, threaten to undermine citizens’ recognition interests by giving the impression that corporations and not citizens wielded ultimate power in society.

  20. I am indebted to Fleischacker (2005: 138) for this observation. The Smith quote is from Book 4, ch. 2.

  21. Note that on this point there is a stronger case for political activity by unions than by corporations since (1) there is generally a much stronger sharing of interests among members of a union than among shareholders and (2) political activity by unions may be one of the most effective ways for those interests to be protected. These shared interests may include, for example, being subject to the arbitrary power of corporations, or generally relying on wages rather than capital.

  22. As Christiano puts it, a “society that includes a large business sector but in which that sector had no voice would be dangerously uninformed about itself.” (247).

  23. In Silver (2012), I argue that businesses have an obligation to reasonably assess whether various stakeholders are vulnerable, and if so to actively consider their interests so as not to take advantage of their vulnerability.

References

  • Austin v. Michigan Chamber of Commerce, (1990). 494 U.S. 652.

  • Beitz, C. (1990). Political equality: An essay in democratic theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brudney, V. (1981). Business corporations and stockholders’ rights under the first amendment. The Yale Law Journal, 91(2), 235–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, A. (1985). Ethics, efficiency, and the market. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christiano, T. (1996). The rule of the many. Boulder: West view Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Citizens United v. Federal Election Commission. (2010). 558 U.S. 310.

  • Crane, A., Matten, D., & Moon, J. (2008). Corporations and citizenship. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson, T., & Dunfee, T. W. (1999). Ties that bind: A social contracts approach to business ethics. Cambridge: Harvard Business School Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, L., Landes, W. M., & Posner, R. A. (2013). How business fares in the supreme court. Minnesota Law Review, 97(5), 1431–1472.

    Google Scholar 

  • First National Bank of Boston v. Bellotti. (1978). 435 U.S. 765.

  • Fleischacker, S. (2005). On Adam smith’s wealth of nations. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, R. E. (2006). Stakeholder theory of the modern corporation (1998) reprinted in Ethical Issues in Business: A philosophical approach. Donaldson and Werhane (eds). 7th edition, pp. 38–48.

  • Gowri, A. (1998). Speech and spending: Corporate political speech rights under the first amendment. Journal of Business Ethics. D 98; 17(16): 1835–1860.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hsieh, N. (2009). Does global business have a responsibility to promote just institutions? Business Ethics Quarterly, 19(2), 251–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hussain, W. (2012). Is ethical consumerism an impermissible form of vigilantism? Philosophy & Public Affairs, 40(2), 111–143.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kumar, R. (1999). Defending the moral moderate: Contractualism and common sense. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 28(4), 275–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kumar, R. (2001). Contractualism on saving the many. Analysis, 61(270), 165–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mufson, S. (2007). Exxon mobil warming up to global climate issue. The Washington Post.

  • Néron, P., & Norman, W. (2008). Citizenship, inc.: Do we really want businesses to be good corporate citizens? Business Ethics Quarterly, 18(1), 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, J. (2008) Supreme Court, Inc. in the March 16, 2008 The New York Times Magazine.

  • Scanlon, T. M. (1998). What we owe to each other. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. M. (2003). The diversity of objections to inequality. In The difficulty of tolerance: Essays in political philosophy. Cambridge, pp. 202–218.

  • Scherer, A. G., & Palazzo, G. (2007). Toward a political conception of corporate social responsibility: Business and society seen from a Haber Asian perspective. Academy of Management Review, 32(4), 1096–1120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Silver, D. (2012). Citizens as Contractualist Stakeholders. Journal of Business Ethics, 109(1), 3–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. (1776). An inquiry into the nature and causes of the wealth of nations.

  • van Oosterhout, J. (Hans). (2008). Transcending the confines of economic and political organization: The misguided metaphor of corporate citizenship. Business Ethics Quarterly, 18(1): 35–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, L. (1997). Ethics and the political activity of business: Reviewing the Agenda. Business Ethics Quarterly, 7(3), 71–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Werhane, P. (1985). Persons, rights, & corporations. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whelan, G. (2012). The political perspective of corporate social responsibility: A critical research Agenda. Business Ethics Quarterly, 22(4), 709–737.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Jamie Hellewell, Rahul Kumar, Matt Bedke, Doran Smolkin and members of the University of Victoria, Department of Philosophy, for helpful discussion of this article.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Silver.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Silver, D. Business Ethics After Citizens United: A Contractualist Analysis. J Bus Ethics 127, 385–397 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-013-2046-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-013-2046-y

Keywords

Navigation