Skip to main content
Log in

Higgs Models and Other Stories about Mass Generation

  • Article
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The paper studies the topography of the model landscape of the physics in the Higgs sector both within the Standard Model of Elementary Particle Physics (SM) and beyond (BSM) in the months before the discovery of a SM Higgs boson. At first glance, this landscape appears fragmented into a large number of different models and research communities. But it also clusters around certain guiding ideas, among them supersymmetry or dynamical symmetry breaking, in which representative and narrative features of the models are combined. These models do not stand for themselves, waiting to be experimentally confirmed and elevated to the status of theory. Rather do they, quite in the sense advocated by Morgan and Morrison, enjoy a far-reaching autonomy. Typically models in the Higgs sector entertain three types of mediating relationships. First, they mediate between the SM and the data in those instances where the SM contains some uncertainty in the values of its basic parameters. Second, they mediate between BSM physics and the data by instantiating the core ideas behind these often speculative generalizations of the SM as stories—in Hartmann’s sense—that motivate or justify the respective model. Third, the fact that Higgs models within BSM physics reproduce the SM predictions in the low-energy limit functions as a consistency constraint that does not involve any additional autonomy. Due to the second type of mediating relationship, the representative features of Higgs models BSM are complex.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The results of both detectors ATLAS and CMS were published simultaneously as Aad et al. (2012) and Chatrchyan et al. (2012).

  2. For a detailed analysis of different senses of theory-ladenness at the example of previous high-energy physics experiments, see Karaca (2013a). Given that the LHC has been devised to both confirm the existence of a Higgs boson and search for new physics, it exhibits both types of theory-ladenness. For even exploratory experimentation is conditioned by what the respective experimental devices are sensitive for.

  3. Cf. Borrelli’s presentation at the CERN seminar available under https://indico.cern.ch/event/232108/.

  4. For a comprehensive overview on these developments, see the contributions in ‘t Hooft (2005).

  5. This comparison does not intend to suggest that the SM had no viable competitors, but points to their common feature of being formulated on the basis of symmetry groups. The SM simply succeeded where others did not, or did not without additional assumptions.

  6. For an overview, see the collection edited by Kuhlmann et al. (2002).

  7. For a brief overview of these developments, see Pickering (1984a, 165–180). A more detailed study of the emergence of the Higgs mechanism is Karaca (2013b).

  8. In the wake of the confirmation of the SM Higgs boson by the LHC, Peter Higgs and François Englert were awarded the 2013 Nobel Prize.

  9. For various statements of physicists to this extent and a more detailed analysis of this charge against the backdrop of philosophical conceptions of adhocness, cf. Friederich et al. (2014).

  10. Private communication from the physicists in our Wuppertal research group at the time of this paper’s revision.

  11. A shorter and less technical version of the presidential address appears as Earman (2004).

  12. Cf. Buchholz (2008).

  13. Cf. Morrison (2003), Liu and Emch (2005), Karaca (2013b).

  14. I leave it to another occasion to discuss whether there is really a simple alternative between axiomatic QFT and Lagrangian QFT, as the recent discussion between Fraser (2011) and Wallace (2011) suggests.

  15. At this point we do not intend a general defense of the semantic view of scientific theories which has recently come under renewed criticism (cf. Halvorson 2012), but focus on its discussion of models in science.

  16. In applied science, such a framework represents a welcome safeguard against surprises, see Stöltzner (2004).

  17. Cf. Morgan and Morrison (1999, 23–24).

  18. Cf. Hartmann (1999, 327).

  19. For a comprehensive overview of the history of QED and the SM, see Schweber (1994), Pickering (1984a), Hoddeson et al. (1997), on which the following resume is based.

  20. Cf. Sect. 2 and Karaca (2013b).

  21. Susskind (1979) argued that the presence of an elementary Higgs field makes the SM ‘unnatural’, recommending his idea of a composite Higgs as a remedy to the naturalness problem. These points were immediately taken up in the mainstream of high energy physics, and constitute today one of the main criticisms against the SM. Both technicolor and supersymmetry claim to offer a solution for it, cf. Susskind (1984).

  22. For an overview of the current state of BSM physics, see, apart from Bustamente’s paper, Rattazzi (2006) and Altarelli (2010).

  23. I am following here Borrelli’s internal report to our research group of June 2012; cf. also Borrelli and Stöltzner (2013).

  24. This class has been analyzed in more detail in Borrelli (2012).

References

  • Aad, G., et al. (2012). Observation of a new particle in the search for the standard model Higgs boson with the ATLAS detector at the LHC. Physics Letters B, 716, 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Altarelli, G. (2010). Particle physics at the LHC start. arXiv:hep-ph/1010.5637v1.

  • Bailer-Jones, D. (2002). Scientists’ thoughts on scientific models. Perspectives on Science, 10(3), 275–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borrelli, A. (2012). The case of the composite Higgs: The model as a “Rosetta stone” in contemporary high-energy physics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 43, 195–214.

  • Borrelli, A., & Stöltzner, M. (2013). Model landscapes in the Higgs sector. In V. Karakostas & D. Dieks (Eds.), EPSA11 perspectives and foundational problems in philosophy of science, the European Philosophy of Science Association Proceedings 2 (pp. 241–252). Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Brading, K., & Castellani, E. (Eds.). (2003). Symmetries in physics: Philosophical reflections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchholz, D. (2008). Quantenfeldtheorie ohne Felder. Ein alternativer Zugang zur Teilchenphysik. Physik-Journal, 7(8/9), 45–50.

  • Buchholz, D., Doplicher, S., Longo, R., & Roberts, J. E. (1992). A new look at Goldstone’s theorem. Reviews in Mathematical Physics, 4((Spec. Issue)), 49–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bustamante, M, Cieri, L. & Ellis, J. (2010). Beyond the standard model for montañeros. arXiv:hep-ph/0911.4409v2.

  • Chatrchyan, S., et al. (2012). Observation of a new Boson at a mass of 125 GeV with the CMS experiment at the LHC. Physics Letters B, 716, 30–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, S., & Weinberg, E. (1973). Radiative corrections as the origin of spontaneous symmetry breaking. Physical Review D, 7, 1888–1910.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cornwall, J. M., & Norton, R. E. (1973). Spontaneous symmetry breaking without scalar mesons. Physical Review D, 8, 3338–3346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J. (2002). Laws, symmetry, and symmetry breaking; invariance, conservation principles, and objectivity. PSA presidential address, http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/878/.

  • Earman, J. (2004). Laws, symmetry, and symmetry breaking: Invariance, conservation principles, and objectivity. Philosophy of Science, 71(5), 1227–1241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fraser, D. (2011). How to take particle physics seriously: A further defense of axiomatic quantum field theory. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 42, 126–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friederich, S., Harlander R., & Karaca, K. (2014). Philosophical perspectives on ad hoc-hypotheses and the Higgs mechanism. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-014-0504-4.

  • Giere, R. N. (1988). Explaining science: A cognitive approach. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (1999). Science without laws. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glashow, S. L. (1961). Partial-symmetries of weak interactions. Nuclear Physics, 22, 579–588.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldstone, J. (1961). Field theories with “superconductor” solutions. Nuovo Cimento, 19, 154–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halvorson, H. (2012). What scientific theories could not be? Philosophy of Science, 79(2), 183–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartmann, S. (1999). Models and stories in hadron physics. In Morgan and Morrison, pp. 326–346.

  • Hoddeson, L., Brown, L., Riordan, M., & Dresden, M. (Eds.). (1997). The rise of the standard model: Particle physics in the 1960s and 1970s. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackiw, R., & Johnson, K. (1973). Dynamical model of spontaneously broken gauge symmetries. Physical Review D, 8, 2386–2398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Karaca, K. (2013a). The strong and weak senses of theory-ladenness of experimentation: Theory-driven versus exploratory experiments in the history of high-energy particle physics. Science in Context, 26(1), 93–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Karaca, K. (2013b). The construction of the Higgs mechanism and the emergence of the electroweak theory. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 44(1), 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhlmann, M., Lyre, H., & Wayne, A. (Eds.). (2002). Ontological aspects of quantum field theory. Singapore: World Scientific.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liu, C., & Emch, G. G. (2005). Explaining quantum spontaneous symmetry breaking. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 36(1), 137–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyre, H. (2008). Does the Higgs mechanism exist? International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 22(2), 119–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyre, H. (2012). The just-so Higgs story: A response to Adrian Wüthrich. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 43, 289–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, M., & Morrison, M. (Eds.). (1999). Models as mediators: Perspectives on natural and social science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Morrison, M. (1999). Models as autonomous agents. In Morgan & Morrison, pp. 38–65.

  • Morrison, M. (2003). Spontaneous symmetry breaking: Theoretical arguments and philosophical problems. In Brading & Castellani, pp. 347–363.

  • Pickering, A. (1984a). Constructing quarks: A sociological history of particle physics. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pickering, A. (1984b). Against putting phenomena first: The discovery of the weak neutral current. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 15, 85–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Randall, L. (2005). Warped Passages. Unraveling the Mysteries of the universe’s hidden dimensions. New York: Ecco.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rattazzi, R. (2006). Physics beyond the standard model. arXiv:hep-ph/0607058v1.

  • Salam, A. (1968). Weak and electromagnetic interactions. In N. Svartholm (Ed.), Elementary particle theory: Relativistic groups and analyticity (pp. 367–377). Stockholm: Almqvist & Wiksell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schweber, S. S. (1994). QED and the men who made it. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smeenk, C. (2006). The elusive Higgs mechanism. Philosophy of Science, 73(5), 487–499.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stöltzner, M. (2004). Application dominance and the model web of plasma physics. In R. Bluhm & C. Nimtz (eds.) Selected papers contributed to the sections of GAP. 5, fifth international congress of the society for analytical philosophy, Bielefeld, 2226 September 2003 (pp. 128–139). (CD-ROM) Paderborn: Mentis.

  • Stöltzner, M. (2012). Constraining the Higgs mechanism: Ontological worries and the prospects for an algebraic cure. Philosophy of Science, 79(5), 930–941.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Struyve, W. (2011). Gauge invariant accounts of the Higgs mechanism. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 42, 226–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Susskind, L. (1979). Dynamics of spontaneous symmetry breaking in the Weinberg-Salam theory. Physical Review D, 20, 2619–2625.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Susskind, L. (1984). The gauge hierarchy problem, technicolor, supersymmetry, and all that. Physics Reports, 104, 181–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ‘t Hooft, G. T. (1971). Renormalizable Lagrangians for massive Yang-Mills fields. Nuclear Physics B, 35, 167–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ‘t Hooft, G. (1980). Naturalness, chiral symmetry, and spontaneous chiral symmetry breaking. In t’ Hooft, G. (ed.), Recent developments in gauge theories. NATO Advanced Science Institutes Series B: Physics 59, 135–157.

  • ‘t Hooft, G. (Ed.). (2005). 50 Years of Yang–Mills theory. Singapore: World Scientific.

    Google Scholar 

  • Veltman, M. (1997). The path to renormalizability. In Hoddeson et al. (1997), pp. 145–178.

  • Wallace, D. (2011). Taking particle physics seriously: A critique of the algebraic approach to quantum field theory. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 42, 116–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, S. (1967). A model of leptons. Physical Review Letters, 19, 1264–1266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, S. (1972). Mixing angle in renormalizable theories of weak and electromagnetic interactions. Physical Review D, 5, 1962–1967.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wüthrich, A. (2012). Eating goldstone bosons in a phase transition: A critical review of Lyre’s analysis of the Higgs mechanism. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 43, 281–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael Stöltzner.

Additional information

This paper has emerged from the research project “The epistemic dynamics of model development at the LHC: an empirical investigation” that was supported by the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (DFG) and is part of the Wuppertal-based research group “Epistemology of the LHC”; see http://www.lhc-epistemologie.uni-wuppertal.de/. Members of the research project were Arianna Borrelli, Robert Harlander, Peter Mättig, Friedrich Steinle, and myself. This paper initially goes back to a presentation at the 2010 “Models and Simulations 4” meeting in Toronto. Earlier drafts were written together with Arianna Borrelli in 2011 and 2012 and submitted to this journal in May 2012; they were drawing upon her continued empirical work in analyzing the model landscape in the Higgs sector and her historical expertise. A shortened and co-authored version has since appeared as Borrelli and Stöltzner (2013). In early 2014, the philosophical part of this paper has been revised so as to reflect the fact that, in July 2012, CERN announced the discovery of a SM Higgs boson and the ongoing debates in our broader research group. I am most grateful to all of them for comments on presentations and earlier drafts of this paper. Borrelli (2012) provides a diachronic analysis of one of the model classes mentioned in the present paper in a somewhat different philosophical perspective.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Stöltzner, M. Higgs Models and Other Stories about Mass Generation. J Gen Philos Sci 45, 369–386 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-014-9259-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-014-9259-3

Keywords

Navigation