Skip to main content
Log in

Perceiving and desiring: a new look at the cognitive penetrability of experience

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper considers an orectic penetration hypothesis (OPH) which says that desires and desire-like states may influence perceptual experience in a non-externally mediated way. This hypothesis is clarified with a definition, which serves further to distinguish the interesting target phenomenon from trivial and non-genuine instances of desire-influenced perception. Orectic penetration is an interesting possible case of the cognitive penetrability of perceptual experience. The OPH is thus incompatible with the more common thesis that perception is cognitively impenetrable. It is of importance to issues in the philosophy of mind and cognitive science, epistemology, and general philosophy of science. The plausibility of orectic penetration can be motivated by some classic experimental studies, and some new experimental research inspired by those same studies. The general suggestion is that orectic penetration thus defined, and evidenced by the relevant studies, cannot be deflected by the standard strategies of the cognitive impenetrability theorist.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. One can think of examples from whatever sport one prefers. Think of a controversial strike called in baseball. Think of a questionable case of the basketball leaving a player’s hand before the buzzer. Think of controversial cases where the ball is close to the line in tennis (perhaps many of John McEnroe’s tantrums were based on a perceptual experience relevantly distinct from the line judge’s). All of these are candidate cases, circumstances where (even upon replay) the image is to some degree ambiguous and relevant desires may influence perceptual experience.

  2. Two brief notes. First, understanding orectic states in this way makes minimal commitments to a theory of desire or of, more broadly, orexis. A number of distinct and incompatible conceptions of desire are consistent with OP, e.g. Armstrong (1980), Smith (1994), Schroeder (2004) and Stalnaker (1984). Second, ‘desire’ will sometimes be used below as shorthand for any orectic state.

  3. It is worth noting that this way of thinking about desire comports with the thinking of potential opponents of OPH—namely, cognitive impenetrability theorists, as discussed below—who include goals, values, and “other utilities” (i.e. other than belief) as possible penetrating cognitive states (i.e. those states that the same thinkers deny can influence perception, and thereby deny the cognitive penetration of, at least some of, perception). See Pylyshyn (1999, p. 343) and Fodor (1983, 1985).

  4. For that matter, some of these cases may be effectively ruled out by clause (1), for example if the causal dependence is understood counterfactually. An olfactory experience of the sea may not depend counterfactually on a desire to smell the sea. You might drag me to the sea, and I would then experience the sea whether or not I had the corresponding desire. Clause (2) thus insures the exclusion of desire-motivated cases involving sophisticated ceteris paribus clauses—clauses to the effect that the context is such that the general causal dependence holds and (1) is satisfied.

  5. According to Fodor, processes are cognitively penetrated if they are “importantly affected by the subject’s beliefs, his background information, or his utilities” (Fodor 1983, p. 73). Given what Fodor says elsewhere, desires seem to be included amongst the relevant cognitive states (e.g. see Fodor 1983, p. 68).

  6. Indeed, OP readily generalizes to a definition of cognitive penetrability by simple replacement of the desire placeholder ‘D’ with a general placeholder for cognitive states.

  7. See Fodor (1983, 1985, 1988), Pylyshyn (1984) and Sperber (1996). See Stokes and Bergeron (MS) for a dilemma for modularity architectures, one horn of which challenges a commitment to informational encapsulation by appeal to the incompatibility with plausible cases of cognitive penetrability of perception.

  8. For a recent survey on theory-laden observation and science, and how it engages with perception and cognitive penetration, see Brewer and Lambert (2001).

  9. An unfortunate ambiguity in this literature is that some use ‘observation’ to refer to perception, others to something more like judgement or belief (about what one perceives).

  10. See Macpherson for additional discussion of possible moves for both Churchland and Fodor (Macpherson, forthcoming). See Siegel for discussion of possible relevant cases of cognitive penetrability, including cases of desire-influenced perception in the context of scientific observation (Siegel, forthcoming).

  11. Siegel presents cognitive penetration as a potential general constraint on theories of epistemic justification. In particular, she argues that dogmatist theories of justification are ill-equipped to meet the constraints imposed by cognitive penetration (Siegel, forthcoming).

  12. The conclusions presented here are experimentally sound, but there is some controversy surrounding a number of additional conclusions drawn by Epstein and others. For related studies and/or criticism, see Lazarus et al. (1953), Saugstad (1966, 1967) and Wolitzky (1967).

  13. One worry regarding this particular study is that the reports of these subjects are not to be trusted (perhaps subjects report seeing the ambiguous figure in just the way that is supposed to result in the desirable beverage). Balcetis and Dunning respond to this worry with a follow up study that uses non-ambiguous figures. In this set up, the subjects identify the non-ambiguous figures with 100% accuracy (no matter whether such identification results in the desirable or undesirable beverage). See Balcetis and Dunning (2006, p. 615).

  14. Elsewhere, Pylyshyn suggests that the allocation of attention is one way that cognition can penetrate perception: it is one of two loci where “cognition intervenes in determining the nature of perception” (Pylyshyn 1999, p. 344). However, the cognitive influence takes place in a way that fails to meet Pylyshyn’s internal, logical connection requirement (of genuine cognitive penetration). So it is unclear why such cases would be considered, by Pylyshyn or anyone else, cognitive penetration. See also Fodor (1988).

  15. Balcetis and Dunning (2010) attempt to control for this possible scenario by introducing an action-based report into later experiments. Here subjects toss an item as a distance estimate (rather than verbally providing a numerical estimate). For this to evade the relevant judgement interpretation, however, one has to make the contentious assumption that visual perception is directly linked with action and in these very kinds of perceptual circumstances.

  16. Macpherson analyzes both the judgement and attention-shift strategies, arguing that both fail to handle data from colour perception studies performed by Delk and Fillenbaum (1965) (see Macpherson, forthcoming).

  17. See Jenkin (1957) and Tajfel (1957) for important theoretical reviews that support this general conclusion.

  18. McCurdy (1956).

  19. Fodor (1988) and Pylyshyn (1999).

  20. Fodor (1983, 1985) and Pylyshyn (1999) both invoke this example.

References

  • Armstrong, D. (1980). The nature of the mind. St. Lucia, QLD: University of Queensland Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balcetis, E., & Dunning, D. (2006). See what you want to see: Motivational influences on visual perception. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 91(4), 612–625.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balcetis, E., & Dunning, D. (2010). Wishful seeing: Desired objects are seen as closer. Psychological Science, 21, 147–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blum, A. (1957). The value factor in children’s size perception. Child Development, 28, 14–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brewer, W. F., & Lambert, B. L. (2001). The theory-ladenness of observation and the theory-ladenness of the rest of the scientific process. Philosophy of Science, 68, 176–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruner, J. S., & Goodman, C. C. (1947). Value and need as organizing factors in perception. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 42, 33–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruner, J. S., & Postman, L. (1948). Symbolic value as an organizing factor in perception. Journal of Social Psychology, 27, 203–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruner, J. S., & Rodrigues, J. S. (1953). Some determinants of apparent size. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 48, 17–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carter, L. F., & Schooler, K. (1949). Value need and other factors in perception. Psychological Review, 56, 200–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1979). Scientific realism and the plasticity of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1988). Perceptual plasticity and theoretical neutrality: A reply to Jerry Fodor. Philosophy of Science, 55, 167–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1989). A neurocomputational perspective: The nature of mind and the structure of science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Delk, J. L., & Fillenbaum, S. (1965). Differences in perceived colour as a function of characteristic color. The American Journal of Psychology, 78, 290–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dukes, W. F., & Bevan, W. (1952). Size estimation and monetary value: A correlation. Journal of Psychology, 34, 43–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, S. (1961). Food-related responses to ambiguous stimuli as a function of hunger and ego strength. Journal of Consulting Psychology, 25, 463–469.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. (1962). Explanation, reduction and empiricism. In H. Feigl & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Minnesota studies in philosophy of science (Vol. 3, pp. 28–97). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1983). Modularity of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1984). Observation reconsidered. Philosophy of Science, 51, 23–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1985). Précis of the modularity of mind. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 8, 1–5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1988). A reply to Churchland’s ‘Perceptual plasticity and theoretical neutrality’. Philosophy of Science, 55, 19–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, N. R. (1958). Patterns of discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, N. R. (1969). Perception and discovery: An introduction to scientific inquiry. San Francisco, CA: Freeman and Cooper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holzkamp, K., & Perlwitz, E. (1966). Absolute oder relative Größenakzentuierung? Eine experimentelle Studie zur sozialen Wahrnehmung. Zeitschrift für Experimentelle und Angewandte Psychologie, 13, 390–405.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jenkin, N. (1957). Affective processes in perception. Psychological Bulletin, 54, 100–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, G. S., Schlesinger, H. J., & Meister, D. E. (1951). The effect of personal values on perception—An experimental critique. Psychological Review, 58, 96–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lazarus, R. S., Yosem, H., & Arenberg, A. (1953). Hunger and perception. Journal of Personality, 21, 312–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lysak, W., & Gilchrist, J. C. (1955). Value, equivocality, and goal availability as determinants of size judgments. Journal of Personality, 23, 500–501.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macpherson, F. (forthcoming). Cognitive penetration of colour experience: Rethinking the issue in light of an indirect mechanism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.

  • McCurdy, H. G. (1956). Coin perception studies and the concept of schemata. Psychological Review, 63, 160–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review, 83, 435–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. (1984). Computation and cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. (1999). Is vision continuous with cognition? The case for cognitive impenetrability of visual perception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22(3), 341–365.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saugstad, P. (1966). Effect of food deprivation on perception-cognition. Psychological Bulletin, 65, 80–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saugstad, P. (1967). Comments on the article by David L. Wolitzky. Psychological Bulletin, 68, 345–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, T. (2004). Three faces of desire. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (forthcoming). Cognitive penetrability and perceptual justification. Nous.

  • Smith, M. (1994). The moral problem. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D. (1996). Explaining culture: A naturalistic approach. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1984). Inquiry. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stokes, D., & Bergeron, V. (unpublished manuscript). A dilemma for modular architectures of the mind.

  • Tajfel, H. (1957). Value and the perceptual judgment of magnitude. Psychological Review, 64, 192–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tajfel, H., & Wilkes, A. L. (1963). Classification and quantitative judgment. British Journal of Psychology, 54, 101–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Ulzen, N. R., Semin, G. R., Oudejans, R., & Beek, P. (2008). Affective stimulus properties influence size perception and the Ebbinghaus illusion. Psychological Research, 72, 304–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolitzky, D. L. (1967). Effect of food deprivation on perception-cognition: A comment. Psychological Bulletin, 68, 342–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

For discussion and feedback, thanks to Paul Bartha, Vince Di Lollo, Catherine Wilson. Special thanks to Vince Bergeron, Fiona Macpherson, Mohan Matthen, and Susanna Siegel for reading (multiple) drafts, and for invaluable conversation on this and related topics. Special thanks also to one anonymous reviewer (for this journal) for exceptionally helpful criticism.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dustin Stokes.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Stokes, D. Perceiving and desiring: a new look at the cognitive penetrability of experience. Philos Stud 158, 477–492 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-010-9688-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-010-9688-8

Keywords

Navigation