In the insightful and provocative book Final Exam, noted author and liver transplant surgeon Pauline Chen chronicles her medical education and some of the ethical dilemmas physicians face in practice.1 She describes a hierarchal and often authoritative system of care, reflecting upon the frailties of care providers as well as patients. Though she does not explicitly use the term, Chen implicitly describes the impact of moral distress on health care quality, providers’ ability to meet professional and ethical obligations, and subsequent provider satisfaction and retention.

Moral distress, as defined by Andrew Jameton in 1984, is the inability of a moral agent to act according to his or her core values and perceived obligations due to internal and external constraints.2 Others have noted the psychological and physical burdens resulting from moral distress.3 Today, nurses and their colleagues face ethical issues that seem more complex and more frequent than when Jameton coined the term twenty-five years ago. Although moral distress was originally conceptualized to address ethical issues in nursing, all health care professionals tackle morally relevant questions pertaining to the “rightness” or “wrongness” of decisions, treatments, or procedures, while feeling powerless to change situations they perceive to be morally wrong. Providers frequently say things like, “It’s not my job to speak out; no one will listen anyway,” or, “This doesn’t make any sense; why are we continuing to do this?,” or “I want to tell the patient to run.”

A case drawn from practice shows the anger, guilt, and moral compromise that health care professionals may experience in situations of moral distress. A thirty-five-year-old woman, Ms. Adams (all names and identifying details have been changed), had been diagnosed with acute lymphocytic leukemia that proved resistant to all standard and experimental chemotherapy regimens. She was divorced, uninsured, and had four young children. Previously hospitalized for fungal pneumonia and sepsis that was compounded by a low white blood cell count from experimental treatment, Ms. Adams returned to the emergency room with abdominal pain, nausea, and vomiting. She was readmitted and diagnosed with a pancreatic abscess and small bowel obstruction; she developed intractable pain and pancytopenia—a form of anemia requiring daily transfusions. She was not a candidate for surgery at this time because of her debilitation.

Ms. Adams and her family met with the team to discuss her options. She refused hospice care in lieu of continuing aggressive treatments like experimental chemotherapy, believing that she would “be healed and pull through this ordeal.” She said that after her blood counts recovered, she wanted to go home to spend time with her children. She chose to remain a “full code” rather than agree to a do-not-resuscitate order. Her parents told the oncology fellow, “She is a fighter and would want to try anything to save her life.”

Jane, Ms. Adams’s primary nurse, struggled to accept these decisions. She had already seen several primary care patients suffer through medically futile chemotherapy. Jane empathized with her patient’s desire to keep fighting for her children, but she doubted Ms. Adams would leave the hospital alive.

A week later, Ms. Adams again developed sepsis, along with blood in her urine, confusion, rapid breathing, and system failure. Jane asked, “Why are we providing false hope to Ms. Adams and her family? This seems senseless. I feel like I’m inflicting unnecessary suffering on her.” The fellow agreed, saying he was also troubled and would not choose this type of treatment for himself or his loved ones. He believed hospice would be the best option for Ms. Adams, but told Jane that his job was to do everything he could to keep her alive, since he must follow his attending physician’s orders and the family’s wishes.

Ms. Adams died two weeks later in the intensive care unit, never making it home to see her children. Her case raises several morally distressing events frequently encountered in daily patient care—feelings of powerlessness, miscommunication, missed opportunities for meaningful end-of-life discussions, confrontational dialogue, implicit deception, and value conflicts related to “hope-driven treatment.”4 Jane and the oncology fellow felt guilt, sadness, and anger. They were concerned that they had failed their patient on several fronts: first, by offering her treatments that they knew would not help her and would only give her toxic side effects; second, by honoring [End Page 20] choices that they would have rejected for themselves; third, by failing to discuss palliative care and hospice options until the patient was too debilitated to return home and spend time with her children; and finally, by failing to confront the attending physician, who refused to discuss end-of-life care with his patient in a meaningful way.

Chen notes that physicians—especially those less experienced or in training—can view “dying [as] a personal failure and withdrawing treatment [as] the declaration of defeat.”5 In this case, the oncology fellow decided that his easiest choice was to simply follow orders; yet by doing so, he created more suffering, both for his patient and for himself. While providers are expected to respect the autonomous right of patients to determine their own best interests, they are not obligated to provide medically futile care. As Edmund Pellegrino and David Thomasma state, “no one can make health professionals do what is thought to be harmful to patients.”6 However, there is no clear point at which a provider can override patient autonomy when he or she is concerned about life-sustaining treatments. When does treatment become more burdensome than beneficial, and who determines that? Empirical evidence suggests that providers face mounting pressures from administrators, colleagues, patients, and families. They question futile treatments, encounter unethical and unprofessional practices, and become emotionally exhausted, frustrated, and disillusioned with their professional practice.7 Certainly, we need to diminish the untoward effects of moral distress.

When providers perceive ethical issues that they can do nothing about, an open dialogue among patients, providers, and administrative personnel is warranted. Interdisciplinary education and collegial practice are two strategies to decrease moral distress. For example, physicians and nurses can benefit from a common ethics course to exchange ideas and learn about each other’s professions and ethical philosophies. Helping students to develop an ethical skill set instills confidence that will allow them to exercise moral convictions when difficult patient care issues arise. In most settings, for example, nurses cannot initiate “do not resuscitate” discussions.8 However, Daniel Sulmasy and colleagues argue that nurses themselves feel capable of initiating these discussions, and that the majority of attending physicians they surveyed agreed that nurses should be permitted to do so.9

Moving to more open collegiality and shared practice models may help to alleviate moral distress by increasing a sense of shared responsibility and of professional satisfaction. As the United States faces major nursing and physician shortages, interdisciplinary education and collegial practices would represent a commitment to seek common ground, garner mutual respect for each other’s roles, and discuss meaningful ways to communicate and collaborate effectively about the ethical problems each group identifies.

Recurrent situations of moral distress indicate underlying systemic problems of poor communication, inadequate collaboration, and perceived powerlessness that must be addressed if we are to minimize this phenomenon in clinical settings.10 Reducing moral distress calls for identifying efficient and effective mechanisms to support health care providers who have limited time to focus on ethical issues but know that the intensity of these events lingers well beyond the occurrence. Many nurses feel the need for pastoral support to provide a comforting presence and listening ear when they experience moral distress. Chaplains and clinical ethics consultants can also intercede when value conflicts between two parties hinder a common goal.

As members of a health care community that the public trusts with their most morally significant treatment decisions, physicians, nurses, and other health care providers have an obligation to speak up about their ethical concerns for the patient’s welfare. Giving voice and recognition to moral distress is the first step.11 Ethical dialogue may provide a sense of resolve and reason to approaching difficult ethical questions that providers encounter when caring for those with complex health care needs. As Chen notes, perhaps we can then become the health care providers we always dreamed of being.

Connie M. Ulrich

Connie M. Ulrich is associate professor of bioethics and nursing in the University of Pennsylvania School of Nursing and member of the Biobehavioral and Health Sciences Division and New Courtland Center for Transitions and Health.

Ann B. Hamric

Ann B. Hamric is a professor in the School of Nursing and a faculty affiliate in the Center for Biomedical Ethics and Humanities at the University of Virginia. She directs the Moral Distress Consultation Service at the UVA Medical Center.

Christine Grady

Christine Grady is deputy and acting chief of the Department of Bioethics at the Clinical Center, National Institutes of Health. She also heads the section on human subjects research.

Acknowledgment

We thank Dr. Sarah Kagan, Reverend Byron Brought, and Terease Waite for their thoughtful and insightful comments about moral distress and Ariella Kopinsky for her editing assistance. The opinions expressed in this manuscript are those of the authors.

References

1. P.W. Chen, Final Exam: A Surgeon’s Reflections on Mortality (New York: Random House, 2007).
2. A. Jameton, Nursing Practice: The Ethical Issues (Englewood, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1984).
3. J.M. Wilkinson, “Moral Distress in Nursing Practice: Experience and Effect,” Nursing Forum 23 (1988): 16–29; A.B. Hamric, W. Davis, and M.D. Childress, “Moral Distress in Health-Care Providers: What Is [End Page 21] It and What Can We Do about It?” Pharos of Alpha Omega Alpha Honor Society 69 (2006): 16–23.
4. Chen, Final Exam.
5. Ibid.
6. E.D. Pellegrino and D.C. Thomasma, The Virtues in Medical Practice (New York: Oxford, 1993).
7. P. Chen, “When Nurses and Doctors Can’t Do the Right Thing,” New York Times, February 5, 2009; A.B. Hamric and L.J. Blackhall, “Nurse-Physician Perspectives on the Care of Dying Patients in Intensive Care Units: Collaboration, Moral Distress, and Ethical Climate,” Critical Care Medicine 35 (2007): 422–29.
8. D.P. Sulmasy, M. Kai He, R. McAuley, and W.A. Ury, “Beliefs and Attitudes of Nurses and Physicians about Do Not Resuscitate Orders and Who Should Speak to Patients and Families about Them,” Critical Care Medicine 36 (2008): 1817–22.
9. Ibid.
10. E. G. Epstein and A.B. Hamric, “Moral Distress, Moral Residue, and the Crescendo Effect,” Journal of Clinical Ethics, forthcoming.
11. Hamric, Davis, and Childress, “Moral Distress in Health Care Providers.”

Share