Skip to main content
Log in

The fantasy of third-person science: Phenomenology, ontology and evidence

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Dennett’s recent defense in this journal of the heterophenomenological method and its supposed advantages over Husserlian phenomenology is premised on his problematic account of the epistemological and ontological status of phenomenological states. By employing Husserl’s philosophy of science to clarify the relationship between phenomenology and evidence and the implications of this relationship for the empirical identification of ‘real’ conscious states, I argue that the naturalistic account of consciousness Dennett hopes for could be authoritative as a science only by virtue of the very phenomenological evidences Dennett’s method consigns to the realm of fiction. Thus heterophenomenology, qua scientific method, is incoherent.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Dennett 1991, 2001, 2002, 2003, and 2007.

  2. It is worth noting that the title Dennett gives to the transcript from which this quote is taken is “The Fantasy of First-Person Science”, despite his assertion quoted above that his method could just have well been called a ‘first-person science of consciousness’.

  3. See the ‘Shakey’ case in Dennett 1991, 85–95 for this conflation, repeated also in Dennett 2007, 257–58.

  4. As Zahavi notes, both Husserl and Merleau-Ponty explicitly rejected the view that the contents of one’s consciousness are inaccessible to others; the contents are not directly accessible in quite the same manner (otherwise there would be no detectable difference between oneself and another), but they are intersubjectively accessible nonetheless. (Zahavi 2007, 32) Nor is the intersubjective access just a matter of the subject’s reporting the content of her mental states, as if the content itself remained concealed from others. Rather, the content is often directly manifest in a public way, through speech, gesture and other bodily expression.

  5. This is why consciousness itself ‘ain’t in the head’, to adapt Putnam’s much-celebrated phrase. There is one further subtlety that cannot be ignored, namely, that among the ‘really inherent’ elements of an experience is the sense of the object as given [in that experience itself]; excluding still the robustly noematic sense of the object as an entity transcendent to that particular experience. Hence the reell contents of consciousness do include the evidences of perception qua evidences, though they do not include as inherent parts the objects made evident in perception. (Husserl 1913, Section 97)

  6. One might of course have indirect evidence of a subject’s lived experience without the testimony of that subject, e.g., EEG indicators of consciousness, however, those have been validated as reliable indicators of consciousness only by correlating their patterns with subjects’ expressions, in speech or other behavior, of first-personal experiences.

  7. See Husserl 1952, Section 53 for his characterization of this tension between perspectives. See also Husserl 1962, 254 for his characterization of natural realism as an attitude embedded within the phenomenological domain of transcendental intersubjectivity.

  8. See also Husserl 1954, 189, 1950, 12, 1929, 205; for related views in cognitive science, see Noë 2004; O’Regan and Noë 2001; Hurley, 1998; Varela et al. 1991.

  9. Certain terms employed liberally in the relevant literature by phenomenologists and physicalists alike are equally confounding: ‘mental life’, ‘real seemings’, and ‘third-person evidence’ chief among them.

  10. Hence while Marbach is right to insist that no one would ever take up the study of consciousness and develop concepts concerning it in the absence of phenomenal experience (Marbach 2007, 76), the conclusion is too narrow: no one would ever take up any study or develop any concepts whatsoever in the absence of phenomenal evidence to motivate that study and validate its concepts.

References

  • Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston: Little, Brown.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2001). The fantasy of first-person science. http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/papers/chalmersdeb3dft.htm.

  • Dennett, D. C. (2002). How could I be wrong? How wrong could I be? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 9(5–6), 13–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2003). Who’s on first? Heterophenomenology explained. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10(9–10), 19–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2007). Heterophenomenology reconsidered. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6, 247–270. DOI 10.1007/s11097-006-9044-9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drummond, J. J. (2007). Phenomenology: neither auto- nor hetero- be. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6, 57–74. DOI 10.1007/s11097-006-9037-8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heelan, P. (1986). Interpretation and the structure of space in scientific theory and in perception. Research in Phenomenology, 16, 187–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S. L. (1998). Consciousness in action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1913 [1976]). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy (First Book). Trans. F. Kersten. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Husserl, E. (1929 [1978]). Formal and transcendental logic. Trans. Dorion Cairns. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, E. (1948 [1973]). Experience and judgment: Investigations in a genealogy of logic. L. Landgrebe (Ed.), trans. James S. Churchill and Karl Ameriks. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Husserl, E. (1950 [1995]). Cartesian meditations: An introduction to phenomenology. Trans. Dorion Cairns. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Husserl, E. (1952 [1989]). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy (Second Book). Trans. R. Rojcewicz and A. Schuwer. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Husserl, E. (1954 [1970]). The crisis of European sciences and transcendental phenomenology: An introduction to phenomenological philosophy. Trans. David Carr. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Husserl, E. (1962). Phanomenologische psychologie. Vorlesungen sommersemester 1925. Husserliana IX. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marbach, E. (2007). No heterophenomenology without autophenomenology: Variations on a theme of mine. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6, 75–87. DOI 10.1007/s11097-006-9027-x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. M. (1964 [1968]). In C. Lefort (Ed.) The visible and the invisible. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2007). The critique of pure phenomenology. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6, 231–245. DOI 10.1007/s11097-006-9043-x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Regan, J. K., & Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor approach to vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24(5), 939–973 Medline.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT .

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2007). Killing the straw man: Dennett and phenomenology. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6, 21–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Shannon Vallor.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Vallor, S. The fantasy of third-person science: Phenomenology, ontology and evidence. Phenom Cogn Sci 8, 1–15 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-008-9092-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-008-9092-4

Keywords

Navigation