Skip to main content
Log in

On the Neglect of the Philosophy of Chemistry

  • Published:
Foundations of Chemistry Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I present a historiography of the recent emergence of philosophy of chemistry. Special attention is given to the interest in this domain in Eastern Europe before the collapse of the USSR. It is shown that the initial neglect of the philosophy of chemistry is due to the unanimous view in philosophy and philosophy of science that only physics is a proper science (to put in Kant's words). More recently, due to the common though incorrect assumption that chemistry can in principle be reduced to physics, the neglect continued, even when interest in sciences such as biology and psychology entered more strongly in philosophy of science. It is concluded that chemistry is an autonomous science and is perhaps a more ‘typical’ science than physics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

REFERENCES

  • B. Abbott, A Note on the Nature of ‘Water’. Mind 106: 311–319, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  • F. Abbri, Lavoisier and the Foundations of Chemistry. In Mosini (Ed.), 1996, pp. 143–154.

    Google Scholar 

  • N.T. Abramova, R.W. Garawenko and E.F. Solonov, Voprosi Filosofii 17(8): 176, 1963.

    Google Scholar 

  • F.M. Akeroyd, A Challenge to the Followers of Lakatos. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 37: 359–362, 1986.

    Google Scholar 

  • F.M. Akeroyd, Research Programmes and Empirical Results. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 39: 51–58, 1988.

    Google Scholar 

  • F.M. Akeroyd, An Oscillatory Model of the Growth of Scientific Knowledge. The British Journal of the Philosophy of Science 41: 407–414, 1990.

    Google Scholar 

  • F.M. Akeroyd, The Challenge to Lakatos Restated. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 39: 437–439, 1990a.

    Google Scholar 

  • F.M. Akeroyd, Laudan's Problem Solving Model. The British Journal of the Philosophy of Science 44: 785–788, 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  • F.M. Akeroyd, Poppers Beitrag für eine Philosophie der Chemie. In K. Ruthenberg and J. Schummer (Eds.), Philosophie der Chemie: Bestandsaufnahme und Ausblick. Königshausen & Neumann, Würzburg, 1996 Psarros et al. (Eds.), 1996, pp. 67–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • F.M. Akeroyd, Conceptual Aspects of Theory Appraisal: Some Biochemical Examples. Hyle 3: 95–102, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  • D. Allchin, A Twentieth-Century Phlogiston: Constructing Error and Differentiating Domains. Perspectives on Science 5: 81–127, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  • A. Amman, Chirality: A Superselection Rule Generated by the Molecular Environment? Journal of Mathematical Chemistry 6: 1–15, 1990.

    Google Scholar 

  • A. Amann, Must a Molecule have a Shape? South African Journal of Chemistry 45: 29–38, 1992.

    Google Scholar 

  • A. Amman, The Gestalt Problem in Quantum Theory: Generation of Molecular Shape by the Environment. Synthese 97: 125–156, 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  • A. Amman, Individual Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics and Quantum Theory of Molecular Shape. In Mosini (Ed.), 1996, pp. 21–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • AN SSSR Der gegenwärtige Stand der Strukturtheorie in der organischen Chemie, translated from the Russian (USSR Academy of Science, Department of Chemical Sciences) by G. Rudakoff and published by the Chemical Society of the DDR (1956), Akademie-Verlag, Berlin, 1954.

  • G. Bachelard, Le pluralisme cohérent de la chimie moderne, 2nd edn. Vrin, Paris, 1975, p. 1932.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Bachelard, Le nouvel esprit scientifique. Alcan, Paris; Presses Universitaires de France, Paris (reprint 1973), 1934.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Bachelard, L'eau et les rêves: essai sur l'imagination de la matière. Corti, Paris, 1942.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Bachelard, Le rationalisme appliqué. Presses Universitaires de France, Paris, 1949.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Bachelard, Épistémologie de la chimie. In Épistémologie. Presses Universitaires de France, Paris, 1971.

    Google Scholar 

  • R.F.W. Bader, P.L.A. Popelier and T.A. Keith, Die theoretische Definition einer funktionellen Gruppe und das Paradigma des Molekülorbitals. Angewandte Chemie 106: 647–659, 1994.

    Google Scholar 

  • W. Balzer, C.-U. Moulines and J.D. Sneed, The Structure of Daltonian Stoichiometry. Erkenntnis 26: 103–127, 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  • D.A. Bantz, The Structure of Discovery: Evolution of Structural Accounts of Chemical Bonding. In T. Nickles (Ed.), Scientific Discovery: Case Studies. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1980, pp. 291–329.

    Google Scholar 

  • A. Baracca, Chemistry's Leading Role in the Scientific Revolution at the Turn of the Century. In Mosini, 1996, pp. 61–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • A. Beckermann, Supervenience, Emergence, and Reduction. In A. Beckermann, H. Flohr and J. Kim (Eds.), Emergence or Reduction? Essays on the Prospects of Nonreductive Physicalism. de Gruyter, Berlin/New York, 1992.

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Bellu, The Dialectical Significance of Chemistry in the Works of Fr. Engels. Revue roumaine des sciences sociales: serie de philosophie et logique 17: 163–169, 1973.

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Bellu, Conservation-transformation au niveau chimique. Revue roumaine des sciences sociales: serie de philosophie et logique 23: 559–569, 1979.

    Google Scholar 

  • O.T. Benfey, Concepts of Time in Chemistry. Journal of Chemical Education 40: 574–577, 1963.

    Google Scholar 

  • A. Benrath, Chemische Grundbegriffe: Eine Erkenntnistheoretische Studie. Chemiker Zeitung 77: 282–286, 1953.

    Google Scholar 

  • B. Bensaude-Vincent, La chimie: un statut toujours problèmatique dans la classification du savoir. Revue de Synthèse 115: 135–148, 1974.

    Google Scholar 

  • B. Bensaude-Vincent and F. Abbri, Lavoisier in European Context: Negotiating a New Language for Chemistry. Science History Publications, Canton, MA, 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  • J.D. Bernal, Science in History, four volumes. Penguin Books, Harmondsworth, 1954.

    Google Scholar 

  • N. Bhushan and S. Rosenfeld, Metaphorical Models in Chemistry. Journal of Chemical Education 72: 578–582, 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  • O.R. Bloch, La Philosophie de Gassendi: Nominalisme, Matérialisme et Métaphysique. Nijhoff, The Hague, 1971.

    Google Scholar 

  • I.M. Bochénski, The Dogmatic Principles of Soviet Philosophy. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1963.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Böhme, Aristotelische Wissenschaft — Aristoteles' Chemie: eine Stoffwechselchemie. In Alternativen der Wissenschaft. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt a/M, 1980, pp. 101–120.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. Bradley, On the Operational Interpretation of Classical Chemistry. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 6: 32–42, 1955.

    Google Scholar 

  • P.W. Bridgman, Reflection of a Physicist. Philosophical Library, New York, NY, 1950.

    Google Scholar 

  • C.D. Broad, The Mind and Its Place In Nature. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London, 1925.

    Google Scholar 

  • J.H. Brooke, Organic Synthesis and the Unification of Chemistry — A Reappraisal. The British Journal for the History of Science 5: 363–392, 1971.

    Google Scholar 

  • S.G. Brush, Why Chemistry Needs History — and How It Can Get Some. Journal of College Science Teaching, May 1978.

  • N.A. Budreiko, Philosophical Problems in Chemistry [in Russian]. Shkola, Moscov, 1970.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Bunge, Is Chemistry a Branch of Physics? Zeitschrift für allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 13: 209–223, 1982.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Bunge, Treatise on Basic Philosophy, vol. 7. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1985, pp. 219–230.

    Google Scholar 

  • J.W. Burbidge, Chemistry and Hegel's Logic. In M.J. Petry (Ed.), Hegel and Newtonianism. Kluwer, Dordrecht, 1993, pp. 609–617.

    Google Scholar 

  • J.W. Burbidge, Real Process: How Logic and Chemistry Combine in Hegel's Philosophy of Nature, 1996.

  • G.V. Bykov, The Origin of the Theory of Chemical Structure. Journal of Chemical Education 39: 220–224, 1962.

    Google Scholar 

  • E.F. Caldin, Theories and the Development of Chemistry. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 10: 209–222, 1959.

    Google Scholar 

  • E.F. Caldin, The Structure of Chemistry in Relation to the Philosophy of Science. Sheed and Ward, London and New York, NY, 1961.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Carrier, Kants Theorie der Materie und ihre Wirkung auf die zeitgenossische Chemie. Kantstudien 81: 170–210, 1990.

    Google Scholar 

  • R. Causey, Unity of Science. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1977.

    Google Scholar 

  • N. Chomsky, Language and Nature. Mind 104: 1–62, 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Christie, Philosophers Versus Chemists Concerning ‘Laws of Nature'. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 25: 613–630, 1994.

    Google Scholar 

  • C.W. Churchman and B.G. Buchanan, On the Design of Inductive Systems: Some Philosophical Problems. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 20: 311–323, 1969.

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Claverie and S. Diner, The Concept of Molecular Structure in Quantum Theory: Interpretation Problems. Israel Journal of Chemistry 19: 54–81, 1980.

    Google Scholar 

  • C.A. Coulson, Recent Developments in Valence Theory. Pure and Applied Chemistry 24: 257–287, 1970.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Del Re, Binding: A Unifying Notion or a Pseudoconcept? International Journal of Quantum Chemistry 19: 1057–1072, 1981.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Del Re, The Historical Perspective and the Specificity of Chemistry. Epistemologia 10: 231–240, 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Del Re, The Specificity of Chemistry and the Philosophy of Science. In Mosini (Ed.), 1996, pp. 11–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • R. Delhez, Bachelard et la chimie. In Bachelard, Publication of the Centre Culturel Internationale de Cerisy-La-Salle, 1974, pp. 121–133.

  • K.G. Denbigh and M.L.G. Redhead, Gibbs' Paradox and Non-Uniform Convergence. Synthese 81: 283–313, 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  • A.M. Diamond, The Polywater Episode and the Appraisal of Theories. In A. Donovan, L. Laudan and R. Laudan (Eds.), Scrutinizing Science. Kluwer, Dordrecht, 1988, pp. 181–198.

    Google Scholar 

  • H. Dingle, The Nature of Scientific Philosophy. Proceedings of the Royal Society of Edinburgh 4: 409, 1949.

    Google Scholar 

  • P.A.M. Dirac, Quantum Mechanics of Many-Electron Systems. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London A123: 714–733, 1929.

    Google Scholar 

  • A. Donovan, and others, The Chemical Revolution: Essays in Reinterpretation, Osiris, 2nd series, volume 4, 1988.

  • A. Drews, Kants Naturphilosophie als Grundlage seines Systems. Mitscher & Röstell, Berlin, 1894.

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Duhem, Le mixte et la combinaison chimique: Essai sur l'évolution d'une idée. Naud, Paris; reprint Fayard, Paris (1985); originally published in Revue de Philosophie 1 (1900) 69–99, 167–197, 331–357, 430–467, 730–745, 1902.

  • A. Duncan, Laws and Order in Eighteenth-Century Chemistry. Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. Dupré, The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  • I. Düring, Aristotle's Chemical Treatise: Meteorologica Book IV. Göteborgs Högskolas Årsskrift, 1944: 2; reprint Garland, New York (1980), 1944.

  • M. Eisvogel, Wem nützt eine Philosophie der Chemie — den Chemikern oder den Philosophen. In K. Ruthenberg and J. Schummer (Eds.), Philosophie der Chemie: Bestandsaufnahme und Ausblick. Königshausen & Neumann, Würzburg, 1996 Psarros et al. (Eds.), 1996, pp. 95–110.

    Google Scholar 

  • B. Ellis, A Comparison of Process and Non-Process Theories in the Physical Sciences. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 8: 45–56, 1957.

    Google Scholar 

  • F. Engels, Dialectics of Nature. International Publishers, New York, NY, 1940.

    Google Scholar 

  • F. Engels, Friedrich Engels über die Dialektik der Naturwissenschafte (texts collected and published by B.M. Kedrov). Pahl-Rugenstein Köln, Dietz, Berlin, 1979.

    Google Scholar 

  • J.D. Farmer, A Rosetta Stone for Connectionism. Physica D 42: 153–187, 1990.

    Google Scholar 

  • J.K. Feibleman, Theory of Integrative Levels. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 5: 59–66, 1954.

    Google Scholar 

  • H. Field, Tarski's Theory of Truth. The Journal of Philosophy 69: 347–375, 1972.

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Francoeur, The Forgotten Tool: The Design and Use of Molecular Models. Social Studies of Science 27: 7–40, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Frank, Foundations of Physics. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL, 1949.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Frické, The Rejection of Avogadro's Hypotheses. In Howson (Ed.), 1976, pp. 277–308.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Fuchs, Erkenntnistheoretische Probleme in der modernen Chemie (Eine Auseinandersetzung mit Georg Maria Schwab). In Philosophische Probleme der Chemie und ihrer Geschichte (published by Technische Hochschule für Chemie “Carl Schorlemmer”). Leuna-Merseburg, 1964, pp. 32–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Fuchs, Theorie und Empirie in der Quantenchemie. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 13 (Sonderheft): 338–344, 1965.

    Google Scholar 

  • R.V. Garkovenko, Philosophical Problems in Modern Chemistry [in Russian]. Moscow, 1970.

  • R.M. Gascoigne, Basic Concepts of Modern Chemistry. In G.H. Aybward (Ed.), Approach to Chemistry. University of South Wales, Sydney, 1961, pp. 68–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • K. Gavroglu, Appropriating the Atom at the End of the 19th Century: Chemists and Physicists at Each Other's Throat. In Mosini (Ed.), 1996, pp. 93–106.

    Google Scholar 

  • K. Gavroglu and A. Simoes, The Americans, the Germans, and the Beginning of Quantum Chemistry: The Confluence of Diverging Traditions. Historical Studies in the Physical and Biological Sciences 25: 47–110, 1994.

    Google Scholar 

  • H. Gay, Radicals and Types. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 7: 1–51, 1976.

    Google Scholar 

  • H. Gay, The Asymmetric Carbon Atom. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 9: 207–308, 1978.

    Google Scholar 

  • R.N. Giere, Cognitive Models of Science. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, MN, 1992.

    Google Scholar 

  • N. Goodman, Ways of Worldmaking. Hackett, Indianapolis, IN, 1978.

    Google Scholar 

  • L.R. Graham, Science and Philosophy in the Soviet Union. Allen Lane, London, 1971.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Gutmann and G. Hanekamp, Abstraktion und Ideation — Zur Semantik chemischer und biologischer Grundbegriffe. Journal for General Philosophy of Science 27: 29–53, 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Gutting, Gaston Bachelard's Philosophy of Science. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 2: 55–71, 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  • W. Haberditzl and H. Laitko, Reduziert sich die theoretische Chemie auf angewandte Quantenmechanik und Quantenphysik? Wissenschaftliche Zeitschrift der Humboldt-Universität Berlin, mathematisch-naturwissenschaftliche Reihe 16: 961–962, 1967.

    Google Scholar 

  • I. Hacking, Representing and Intervening. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1983.

    Google Scholar 

  • P.J. Hall, The Pauli Exclusion Principle and the Foundations of Chemistry. Synthese 68: 267–272, 1986.

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Han, Die Notwendigkeit einer Philosophie der Chemie. In K. Ruthenberg and J. Schummer (Eds.), Philosophie der Chemie: Bestandsaufnahme und Ausblick. Königshausen & Neumann, Würzburg, 1996 Psarros et al. (Eds.), 1996, pp. 59–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Hartmann, Die philosophische Grundlagen der Naturwissenschaften. Fischer, Jena, 1948.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Heber, Eine Bemerkung über die quantenmechanische Theorie der Valenz. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 12: 985–986, 1964.

    Google Scholar 

  • W. Heisenberg, Ordnung der Wirklichkeit (quoted from his Gesammelte Werke, Physik und Erkenntnis 1927–1955). Piper, München/Zürich, 1942.

    Google Scholar 

  • W. Heisenberg, Physik und Philosophie. Hirzel, Stuttgart, 1959.

    Google Scholar 

  • C.G. Hempel, Aspects of Scientific Explanation. Macmillan, London, 1965.

    Google Scholar 

  • H. Hettema and T.A. Kuipers, The Periodic Table — Its Formalization, Status, and Relaton to Atomic Theory. Erkenntnis 28: 387–408, 1988.

    Google Scholar 

  • R. Hoffmann and P. Laszlo, Representation in Chemistry. Angewandte Chemie Int. Ed. Engl. 30: 1–16, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • R. Hoffmann, V.I. Minkin and B.K. Carpenter, Ockham's Razor and Chemistry. Bulletin de la Société Chimique de France 133: 117–130 [also: Hyle 3: 3–28], 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  • J.R. Hofmann, How the Models of Chemistry Vie. PSA 1990 1: 405–419, 1990.

    Google Scholar 

  • J.R. Hofmann and P.A. Hofmann, Darcy's Law and Structural Explanation in Hydrology. PSA 1992 1: 23–35, 1992.

    Google Scholar 

  • R. Hooykaas, The Concepts of ‘Individual’ and 'species’ in Chemistry. Centaurus 5: 307–322, 1958.

    Google Scholar 

  • C. Howson (Ed.), Method and Appraisal in the Physical Sciences. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1976.

    Google Scholar 

  • C. Howson and A. Franklin, Maher, Mendeleev and Bayesianism. Philosophy of Science 58: 574–585, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • P.P. Ionidi, The Philosophical Significance of the Periodic Law of Mendeleev [in Russian]. “Enanie”, Moscow, 1958.

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Janich, Chemie als Kulturleistung. Zum Selbstverständnis der Chemie im Spiegel der Kulturgeschichte”. In G. Stock, Chemie und Geisteswissenschaften. Akademie Verlag, Berlin, 1992 Mittelstraß and Stock (Eds.), 1992, pp. 161–173.

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Janich, Protochemie: Programm einer konstruktiven Chemiebegründung. Journal for General Philosophy of Science 22: 71–87 [also in: Chimica Didactica 21 (1995) 111–128], 1994.

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Janich (Ed.), Philosophische Perspektiven der Chemie. BI-Wissenschaftsverlag, Mannheim, 1994a.

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Janich and N. Psarros (Eds.), Die Sprache der Chemie. Königshausen & Neumann, Würzburg, 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Johnston, Manifest Kinds. The Journal of Philosophy 94: 564–583, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Jordan, Das Bild der modernen Physik. Ullstein, Frankfurt a/M, 1957 [1947].

    Google Scholar 

  • A. Kamlah, A Logical Investigation of the Phlogiston Case. In W. Balzer et al. (Eds.), Reduction in Science. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1984, pp. 217–238.

    Google Scholar 

  • I. Kant, Gesammelte Schriften. Berlin Academy of Science, Berlin, 1902-.

    Google Scholar 

  • B.M. Kedrov, Dalton's Atomic Theory and Its Philosophical Significance. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 9: 644–662, 1949; translated from Bull. Acad. Sci. Hist. Phil. Series 4(6): 487–504, 1947.

    Google Scholar 

  • B.M. Kedrov, Spektralanalyse. VEB, Berlin, 1956.

    Google Scholar 

  • B.M. Kedrov, Über das Verhältnis der Bewegungsformen der Materie in der Natur. In Philosophische Probleme der modernen Naturwissenschaft. VEB, Berlin, 1962.

    Google Scholar 

  • B.M. Kedrov, Tri aspekta atomistiki, vol. I: Paradoks Gibbsa, vol II: Uchenie Dalt'ona, vol. III: Zakon Mendeleeva. Moscow, 1969.

  • W. Kent, Scientific Naming. Philosophy of Science 25: 185–194, 1958.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. Kim, Mental Causation: What? Me Worry? In E. Villanueva (Ed.), Contents. Ridgeview, Atascadero, 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  • A.I. Kitaigorodsky, Theoretical Problems of Chemistry [in Russian]. Voprosi Filosofii 20: 75–87, 1966.

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Kitcher, Theories, Theorists and Theoretical Change. The Philosophical Review 87: 519–547, 1978.

    Google Scholar 

  • U. Klein, Origin of the Concept of Chemical Compound. Science in Context 7: 163–204, 1994.

    Google Scholar 

  • U. Klein, Robert Boyle: Der Begründer der neuzeitlichen Chemie. Philosophia Naturalis 31: 63–106, 1994a.

    Google Scholar 

  • S. Körner, On Kant's Conception of Science and the Critique of Practical Reason. Kantstudien 82: 173–178, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • G.M. Kosolapoff and G.W. Wheland, Letters to Chemical and Engineering News 30: 2474, 1952.

    Google Scholar 

  • S. Kripke, Naming and Necessity. Blackwell, Oxford (1980), 1972.

    Google Scholar 

  • H.H. Kubbinga, Les première spécification dite ‘moléculaire’ de l'atomisme épicurien: Isaac Beeckman (1620) et Sébastien Basson (1621): Le concept d'individu substantiel et de d'espèce substantielle. Revue d'Histoire des Sciences 37: 215–233, 1984.

    Google Scholar 

  • H.H. Kubbinga, The First ‘Molecular’ Theory (1620): Isaac Beeckman (1588–1637). Journal of Molecular Structure (Theochem) 181: 205–218, 1988.

    Google Scholar 

  • T.S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, volume II, Number 2, The University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL, 1962. 2nd enlarged edition 1970.

    Google Scholar 

  • J.H. Kultgen, Philosophic Conceptions in Mendeleev's, Principles of Chemistry, Philosophy of Science 25: 177–184, 1958.

    Google Scholar 

  • D.N. Kursanov, M.G. Gonikberg, B.M. Dbinin, M.I. Kabachnik, E.D. Kaverzneva, E.N. Prilezhaeva, N.D. Sokolov and R. KH. Freidlina, K voprosu o sovremennom sostoianii teorii khimicheskogo stroeniia. Uspekhi Khimii 19: 529–544, 1950; translated as: The present state of the chemical structural theory, Journal of Chemical Education 29: 2–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • V.I. Kuznetsov, On discreteness and Continuity in the Chemical Organisation of Substances [in Russian]. Voprosi Filosofii 10: 61–70, 1963.

    Google Scholar 

  • V.I. Kuznetsov, About the Nature of Qualitative Chemical Changes [in Russian]. Voprosi Filosofii 11: 94–102, 1964.

    Google Scholar 

  • V.I. Kuznetsov and A. Shamin, Butlerov and A. Kekulé's Contributions to the Formation of Structural Organic Chemistry. In J.H. Wotiz (Ed.), The Kekulé Riddle: A Challenge for Chemists and Psychologists, 1993, pp. 211–222.

  • V.I. Kuznetsov and A.A. Pechenkin, Conceptual Problems of Chemistry: The Theory of Resonance [in Russian]. Voprosi Filosofii 5: 75–86, 1972.

    Google Scholar 

  • H. Laitko, Zum Verhältnis von Chemie und Physik”. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 13 (Sonderheft): 330–338, 1965.

    Google Scholar 

  • H. Laitko, Philosophische Fragen der Chemie. Einführung in die Problemsituation. In M. Guntau and H. Wendt (Eds.), Naturforschung und Weltbild. Eine Einführung in philosophische Probleme der modernen Naturwissenschaften. VEB, Berlin, 1967, pp. 107–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • H. Laitko, Chemie und Philosophie: Anmerkungen zur Entwicklung des Gebietes in der Geschichte der DDR. In K. Ruthenberg and J. Schummer (Eds.), Philosophie der Chemie: Bestandsaufnahme und Ausblick. Königshausen & Neumann, Würzburg, 1996 Psarros et al. (Eds.), 1996, pp. 37–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • H. Laitko and W.-D. Sprung, Chemie und Weltanschauung: Standpunkte der marxistischen Philosophie zu einigen philosophischen Problemen der modernen Chemie, 2nd edition 1973. Urania, Leipzig-Jena-Berlin, 1970.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. LaPorte, Chemical Kind Term Reference and the Discovery of Essence. Nous 30: 112–132, 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Laszlo, La parole des choses ou le language de la chimie. Hermann, Paris, 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  • B. Latour, Science in Action. Open University, Milton Keynes, 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  • L. Laudan, Science and Values: The Aims of Science and Their Role in Scientific Debate. University of California Press, Berkeley, CA, 1984.

    Google Scholar 

  • B. Lauth, Reference Problems in Stoichiometry. Erkenntnis 30: 339–62, 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  • B. Lauth, Physical Constants and Reference Dynamics. Journal for General Philosophy of Science 24: 63–86, 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  • A.L. Lavoisier, Traité élémentaire de chimie. Cuchet, Paris, 1789; Principles of Chemistry (Edinburgh, 1790); also in OEuvres de Lavoisier. Imprimerie Impériale, Paris (1864).

    Google Scholar 

  • R. Le Poidevin, The Chemistry of Space. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 72: 77–88, 1994.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Lévy, Les relations entre chimie et physique et le problème de la réduction. Epistemologia 2: 337–70, 1979.

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Lewis, Introduction to Alexander of Aphrodisias: On Aristotle Meteorology 4. Duckworth, London, 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  • C. Liegener and G. Del Re, The Relation of Chemistry to Other fields of Science: Atomism, Reductionism, and Inversion of Reduction. Epistemologia 10: 269–284, 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  • C. Liegener and G. Del Re, Chemistry vs. Physics, the Reduction Myth and the Unity of Science. Zeitschrift für allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 18: 165–174, 1987a.

    Google Scholar 

  • C.-M. Liegener, Die Stellung der Chemie zur Physik — Symptome des Reduktionismus. In Janich (Ed.), 1994.

    Google Scholar 

  • A. Maccoll, Space and Time in Chemistry. Lewis, London, 1964.

    Google Scholar 

  • D.K.C. MacDonald, Physics and Chemistry: Comments on Caldin's View of Chemistry. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 11: 222–223, 1960.

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Maher, Howson and Franklin on Prediction. Philosophy of Science 60: 329–340, 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  • K. Mainzer, Symmetry and Complexity: Fundamental Concepts of Research in Chemistry. Hyle 3: 29–49, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  • U. Majer, Ist die Sprache der Chemie eine Begriffsschrift in Freges Sinne? In N. Psarros (Eds.), Die Sprache der Chemie. Königshausen & Neumann, Würzburg, 1996 Janich and Psarros (Eds.), 1996, pp. 91–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • W.M. Malisoff, Chemistry: Emergence Without Mystification. Philosophy of Science 8: 39–52, 1941.

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Manzelli, To What Extent do We Understand Chemical Reactions? In Mosini (Ed.), 1996, pp. 133–142.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Marino (Ed.), Storia e Fondamenti della Chimica. Accademia Nazionale delle Scienze, Roma, 1994.

    Google Scholar 

  • J.G. McEvoy, Lavoisier, Priestley, and the Philosophes: Epistemic and Linguistic Dimensions to the Chemical Revolution. Man and Nature 8: 91–98, 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Jones McAllester, Gaston Bachelard, Subsersive Humanist: Texts and Readings. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, WI, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • J.W. McAllister, Scientific Realism and the Criteria for Theory-Choice. Erkenntnis 38: 203–222, 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  • L. McIntyre, Gould on Laws in Biological Sciences. Biology and Philosophy 12: 357–367, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  • D.H. Mellor, Natural Kinds. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 28: 299–312, 1977.

    Google Scholar 

  • D. Mendeleev, The Periodic Law of the Chemical Elements. Faraday Lectures. Chemical Society, London, 1889.

    Google Scholar 

  • É. Meyerson, Explanation in the Sciences. Kluwer, Dordrecht, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • É. Meyerson, Identity and Reality. Allen & Unwin, London, 1930.

    Google Scholar 

  • A. Mittasch, Von der Chemie zur Philosophie. Ebner, Ulm/Donau, 1948.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. Mittelstraß and G. Stock, Chemie und Geisteswissenschaften. Akademie Verlag, Berlin, 1992.

    Google Scholar 

  • V. Mosini, Some Considerations on the Reducibility of Chemistry to Physics. Epistemologia 17: 205–223, 1994.

    Google Scholar 

  • V. Mosini, Fundamentalism, Antifundamentalism, and Gibbs's Paradox. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 26: 151–162, 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  • V. Mosini (Ed.), Philosophers in the Laboratory. Euroma/Musis/Accademia Nazionale di Scieze Lettere e Arti Modena, Rome, 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  • V. Mosini, Chemical Properties, Inherent Relations and the Structure of Science. In Mosini (Ed.), 1996, 1996a, pp. 107–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • J.J. Mulckhuyse, Molecules and Models. Synthese 12: 257–275, 1961; reprint: in The Concept and the Role of the Model in Mathematics and Natural and Social Sciences. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp. 133–151.

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Nagel, The Structure of Science. Harcourt, Brace and World, London, 1961.

    Google Scholar 

  • A.C. Nayak and E. Sotnak, Kant on the Impossibility of the “Soft Sciences”. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55: 133–151, 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Needham, Stuff. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71: 270–290, 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Needham, Aristotelian Chemistry: A Prelude to Dumeian Metaphysics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 27: 251–270, 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Needham, Macroscopic Objects: An Exercise in Duhemian Ontology. Philosophy of Science 63: 205–224, 1996a.

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Needham, Substitition: Duhem's Explication of a Chemical Paradigm. Perspectives on Science 4: 408–433, 1996b.

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Needham, Duhem's Physicalism. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 29: 33–62, 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Needham, Reduction and Abduction in Chemistry — A Response to Scerri. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, forthcoming, 1999.

  • G. Nerlich, On the One Hand: Reflections on Enantiomorphy. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 73: 432–443, 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  • U. Niedersen, Chemie heute: Bemerkungen zur Klassifikation der Naturwissenschaften. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 31: 363–373, 1983.

    Google Scholar 

  • U. Niedersen, Prozeßstrukturen: Schellings Philosophie und einige ausgewählte Theorie-und Praxisbereiche der Physikochemie. Selbstorganisation 5: 183–199, 1994.

    Google Scholar 

  • R. Nola, Fixing the Reference of Theoretical Terms. Philosophy of Science 47: 505–531, 1980.

    Google Scholar 

  • M.J. Nye, From Chemical Philosophy to Theoretical Chemistry. Dynamics of Matter and Dynamics of Disciplines 1800–1950. University of California Press, Berkeley, CA, 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  • W. Ostwald, Vorlesungen Ueber Naturphilosophie; Natural Philosophy. London (1911), 1902.

  • W. Ostwald, Prinzipien der Chemie; The Fundamental Principles of Chemistry. London (1909), 1907.

  • F.A. Paneth, The Epistemological Status of the Chemical Concept of Element. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 13: 1–14, 144–160, 1962; originally published in German as Über die erkenntnistheoretische Stellung des Elementbegriffs, Schriften der Königsberger Gelehrten Gesellschaft, naturwissenschaftliche Klasse 8(4): (1931) 101–125.

    Google Scholar 

  • L. Paolini, Quantum Mechanics and the Logical Structure of Contemporary Chemistry. In Current Aspects of Quantum Chemistry. Elsevier, Amsterdam, 1981, pp. 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • L. Pauling, The Place of Chemistry in the Integration of the Sciences. Main Currents in Modern Thought 7: 108–111, 1950.

    Google Scholar 

  • L. Pauling, Teoriia rezonansa v khimii. Zhurnal vsesoiuznogo khimicheskogo obshchestva im. D.I. Mendeleeva 4: 462–467, 1962.

    Google Scholar 

  • L. Pauling, Leben und Tod im Atomzeitalter. VEB, Berlin, 1964.

    Google Scholar 

  • R. Pilkington, Robert Boyle: Father of Chemistry. Murray, London, 1959.

    Google Scholar 

  • N.W. Pirie, Concepts Out of Context. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 2: 269–280, 1952.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Polanyi, Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL, 1958.

    Google Scholar 

  • S. Poller, Zur Abgrenzung und Charakteristik der chemischen Bewegungsform der Materie. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 14: 328–338, 1966.

    Google Scholar 

  • C.E. Prélat, Epistemología de la Química. Espasa and Calpe Argentina, Buenos Aires and Mexico, 1947.

    Google Scholar 

  • H. Primas, Chemistry, Quantum Mechanics and Reductionism: Perspectives in Theoretical Chemistry. Springer, Berlin, 1983.

    Google Scholar 

  • H. Primas, Kann Chemie auf Physik reduziert werden? I. Das molekulare Programm. Chemie unser Zeit 19: 109–119; 160–166, 1985.

    Google Scholar 

  • H. Primas, Reductionism: Palaver Without Precedent. In E. Agazzi (Ed.), The Problems of Reductionism in Science. Kluwer, Dordrecht, 1991, pp. 161–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • N. Psarros, Sind die Gesetze der konstanten und der multiplen Proportionen empirische Naturgesetze oder Normen? In Janich (Ed.), 1994, pp. 53–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • N. Psarros, The Constructive Approach to the Philosophy of Chemistry. Epistemologia 18: 27–38, 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  • N. Psarros, Stoffe, Verbindungen und Elemente — Eine methodische Annäherung an die Gegenstände der Chemie. Chimica didactica 21: 129–148, 1995a.

    Google Scholar 

  • N. Psarros, The Mess with Mass Terms. In Mosini (Ed.), 1996, pp. 123–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • N. Psarros, Die Chemie als Gegenstand philosophischer Reflexion. In K. Ruthenberg and J. Schummer (Eds.), Philosophie der Chemie: Bestandsaufnahme und Ausblick. Königshausen & Neumann, Würzburg, 1996 Psarros et al. (Eds.), 1996, 1996a, pp. 111–141.

    Google Scholar 

  • N. Psarros, K. Ruthenberg and J. Schummer (Eds.), Philosophie der Chemie: Bestandsaufnahme und Ausblick. Königshausen & Neumann, Würzburg, 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  • H. Putnam, The Meaning of Meaning. In his Mind, Language and Reality [Philosophical Papers Volume 2]. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1975, pp. 215–271.

    Google Scholar 

  • H. Putnam, Meaning and theMoral Sciences. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, 1978.

    Google Scholar 

  • H. Putnam, Is Water Necessarily H2O? In his Realism with a Human Face. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1990, pp. 54–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • A. Pyle, Atomism and Its Critics: From Democritus to Newton. Thoemes Press, Bristol, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  • J.L. Ramsey, Beyond Numerical and Causal Accuracy: Expanding the Set of Justificational Criteria. PSA 1990 1: 485–99, 1990.

    Google Scholar 

  • J.L. Ramsey, On Refusing to be an Epistemologically Black Box: Instruments in Chemical Kinetics During the 1920s and '30s. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 23: 283–304, 1992.

    Google Scholar 

  • J.L. Ramsey, Ideal Reaction Types and the Reactions of Real Alloys. PSA 1994 1: 149–159, 1994.

    Google Scholar 

  • J.L. Ramsey, Molecular Shape, Reduction, Explanation and Approximate Concepts. Synthese 111: 233–251, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  • H. Reichenbach, The Aims and Methods of Physical Knowledge. In M. Reichenbach and R.S. Cohen (Eds.), Hans Reichenbach: Selected Writings 1909–1953 (principal translations by E.H. Schneewind), volume II. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1978 [1929], pp. 81–225.

    Google Scholar 

  • K.-H. Richter and H. Laitko, Zur Gegenstandsbestimmung der Chemie. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 10: 1278–1293, 1962.

    Google Scholar 

  • A.J. Rocke, Kekulé, Butlerov, and the Historiography of the Theory of Structure. The British Journal for the History of Science 14: 27–57, 1981.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Röhler, Zur erkenntnistheoretischen Bedeutung von Hypothese, Modellvorstellung und Theorie in der Chemie. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 10: 1294–1307, 1962.

    Google Scholar 

  • A. Rosenberg, Instrumental Biology and the Disunity of Science. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL, 1994.

    Google Scholar 

  • A. Rosenthal, Zu einigen Aspekten des Verhältnisses von Physik und Chemie. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 30: 576–590, 1982.

    Google Scholar 

  • D. Rothbart, Discovering Natural Kinds Through Inter-Theoretic Prototypes. Methodology and Science 26: 171–189, 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  • D. Rothbart, Spectrometers as Analogues of Nature. Philosophy of Science Association (PSA) 1: 141–148, 1994.

    Google Scholar 

  • D. Rothbart and I. Scherer, Kant's Critique of Judgment and the Scientific Investigation of Matter. Hyle 3: 65–80, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  • D. Rothbart and S.W. Slayden, The Epistemology of a Spectrometer. Philosophy of Science 61: 25–38, 1994.

    Google Scholar 

  • K. Ruthenberg, Warum ist die Chemie ein Stiefkind der Philosophie? In K. Ruthenberg and J. Schummer (Eds.), Philosophie der Chemie: Bestandsaufnahme und Ausblick. Königshausen & Neumann, Würzburg, 1996 Psarros et al. (Eds.), 1996, pp. 27–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • K. Ruthenberg, Friedrich Adolf Paneth. Hyle 3: 103–106, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  • H. Sankey, Translation Failure Between Theories. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 22: 223–236, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • E.R. Scerri, The Electronic Configuration Model, Quantum Mechanics and Reduction. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 42: 309–325, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • E.R. Scerri, Chemistry, Spectroscopy, and the Question of Reduction. Journal of Chemical Education 68: 122–126, 1991a.

    Google Scholar 

  • E.R. Scerri, Correspondence and Reduction in Chemistry. In S. French and H. Kamminga (Eds.), Correspondence, Invariance and Heuristics. Kluwer, Dordrecht/Boston/London, 1993, pp. 45–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • E.R. Scerri, Has Chemistry Been at Least Approximately Reduced to Quantum Mechanics. PSA 1994 1: 160–170, 1994.

    Google Scholar 

  • E.R. Scerri, The Exclusion Principle, Chemistry and Hidden Variables. Synthese 102: 165–169, 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  • E.R. Scerri, Has the Periodic Table Been Successfully Axiomatised? Erkenntnis 47: 229–243, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  • E.R. Scerri, The Periodic Table and the Electron. American Scientist 85: 546–553, 1997a.

    Google Scholar 

  • E.R. Scerri, Popper's Naturalised Approach to the Reduction of Chemistry. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 12: 33–44, 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  • E.R. Scerri and L. McIntyre, The Case for the Philosophy of Chemistry. Synthese 111: 213–232, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  • E.W.J. von Schelling, Ideas for a Philosophy of Nature (translated by E.E. Harris and P. Heach from the first German edition 1797). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1988.

    Google Scholar 

  • P.A. Schilpp (Ed.), The Philosophy of C.D. Broad. Tudor, New York, NY, 1959.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. Schröder, Emergence: Non-Reducibility or Downwards Causation? The Philosophical Quarterly 48: 433–452, 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. Schummer, Realismus und Chemie: Philosophische Untersuchungen der Wissenschaft von den Stoffen. Königshausen & Neumann, Würzburg, 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. Schummer, Bibliographic chemiephilosophischer Literatur der DDR. Hyle 2: 3–11, 1996a.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. Schummer, Zur Semiotik der chemischen Zeichensprache: Die Repräsentation dynamischer Verhältnisse mit statischen Mitteln. In N. Psarros (Eds.), Die Sprache der Chemie. Königshausen & Neumann, Würzburg, 1996 Janich and Psarros (Eds.), 1996, 1996c, pp. 113–126.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. Schummer, Towards a Philosophy of Chemistry. Journal for General Philosophy of Science 28: 307–335, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. Schummer, Scientometric Studies on Chemistry I: The Exponential Growth of Chemical Substances, 1800–1995. Scientometrics 39: 107–123, 1997a.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. Schummer, Scientometric Studies on Chemistry II: Aims and Methods of Producing New Chemical Substances. Scientometrics 39: 125–140, 1997b.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. Schummer, Challenging Standard Distinctions Between Science and Technology: The Case of Preparative Chemistry. Hyle 3: 81–94, 1997c.

    Google Scholar 

  • J.R. Searle, Intentionality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1983.

    Google Scholar 

  • W. Sellars, Science, Perception and Reality. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, 1963.

    Google Scholar 

  • M.I. Shakparonov, Outlines of the Philosophical Problems of Chemistry [in Russian]. Moscow University Press, Moscow, 1957.

    Google Scholar 

  • M.I. Shakparonov, Philosophical Chemistry [in Russian]. Government Publisher for Political Literature, Moscow, 1962; published as Chemie und Philosophie (mimeographed). Institute for Marxism-Leninism, Technische Hochschule für Chemie in Leuna-Merseburg, 1963.

    Google Scholar 

  • D. Shapere, Reason and the Search for Knowledge: Investigations in the Philosophy of Science. Reidel, Boston, MA, 1984.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. Shelton, Seeing and Paradigms in the Chemical Revolution. Philosophy of Science (Tucson) 6: 129–141, 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  • R. Simon, Dialektik und Chemie. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 23: 980–984, 1975.

    Google Scholar 

  • R. Simon, U. Niedersen and G. Kertscher, Philosophische Probleme der Chemie. VEB, Berlin, 1982.

    Google Scholar 

  • L. Sklar, Physics and Chance: Philosophical Issues in the Foundations of Statistical Mechanics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  • H.A.M. Snelders, The Significance of Hegel's Treatment of Chemical Affinity. In M.J. Petry (Ed.), Hegel and Newtonianism. Kluwer, Dordrecht, 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  • I. Stengers, Ambiguous Affinity: The Newtonian Dream of Chemistry in the Eighteenth Century. In M. Serres (Ed.), A History of Scientific Thought: Elements of a History of Science. Blackwell, Oxford, 1995, pp. 372–400.

    Google Scholar 

  • H. Stork, Über die Diskussion und Ablehning der Resonanz-Mesomerie-Theorie in der Sowjetunion. Chemiker-Ztg./Chem. Apparatur 87: 608–619, 1963.

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Ströker, Denkwege der Chemie — Elemente ihrer Wissenschaftstheorie. Alber, Freiburg, 1967.

    Google Scholar 

  • B.T. Sutcliffe, The Development of the Idea of a Chemical Bond. International Journal of Quantum Chemistry 58: 645–656, 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  • V.M. Tatevskii and M.I. Shakhparanov, Ob odnoi makhistskoi teorii v khimii i ee propagandistakh. Voprosi Filosofii 3: 176–192, 1949; excerpts translated as “About a Machistic theory in chemistry and its propagandists” in Journal of Chemical Education 29: 14–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Thagard, Explanatory Coherence. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12: 435–502, 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Thagard, The Conceptual Structure of the Chemical Revolution. Philosophy of Science 57: 183–209, 1990.

    Google Scholar 

  • D.W. Theobald, Some considerations on the philosophy of chemistry. Chemical Society Reviews 5: 203–213, 1976.

    Google Scholar 

  • D.W. Theobald, Gaston Bachelard et la philosophie de la chimie. Archives de philosophie 45: 63–83, 1982.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Tijiattas, Bachelard and Scientific Realism. Philosophical Forum (Spring): 203–210, 1991.

  • M. Tiles, Bachelard: Science and Objectivity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1985.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Tiles, Epistemological History: The Legacy of Bachelard and Canguilhem. Philosophy 21(Suppl.): 141–156, 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. Timmermans, The Concept of Species in Chemistry. Chemical Publishing Company, New York, NY, 1963; revised translation of La notion d'espèce chimie (Paris 1928).

    Google Scholar 

  • S.E. Toulmin, Crucial Experiments: Priestley and Lavoisier. Journal of the History of Ideas 18: 205–220, 1957.

    Google Scholar 

  • C. Trindle, The Hierarchy of Models in Chemistry. Croatica Chemica Acta 57: 1231–1245, 1984.

    Google Scholar 

  • R. Tursman, Phanerochemistry and Semiotic. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 25: 453–468, 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. van Brakel, The Chemistry of Substances and the Philosophy of Natural Kinds. Synthese 69: 291–324, 1986.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. van Brakel, Units of Measurement: Some Kripkean Considerations. Erkenntnis 33: 297–317, 1990.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. van Brakel, Chemistry. Handbook of Metaphysics and Ontology. München: Philosophia Verlag 1: 146–147, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. van Brakel, Polywater and Experimental Realism. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44: 775–784, 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. van Brakel, Interdiscourse or Supervenience Relations: The Priority of the Manifest Image. Synthese 106: 253–297, 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. van Brakel, Chemistry as the Science of the Transformation of Substances. Synthese 111: 253–282, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. van Brakel, Interculturele Communicatie en Multiculturalisme: Enige Filosofische Voorbemerkingen. van Gorcum, Assen, 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. van Brakel, Supervenience and Anomalous Monism. Dialectica 53: 1–24, 1999.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. van Brakel, The Nature of Chemical Substances, forthcoming in a book to be published by Oxford University Press (edited by N. Bhushan and S. Rosenfeld), 1999a.

  • J. Van Cleve and R.E. Frederick, The Philosophy of Right and Left: Incongruent Counterparts and the Nature of Space. Kluwer, Dordrecht, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • P.E. van der Vet, The Debate Between F.A. Paneth, G. von Hevesy, and K. Fajans on the Concept of Chemical Identity. Janus 66: 285–303, 1979.

    Google Scholar 

  • P.E. van der Vet, The Aborted Takeover of Chemistry by Physics. Ph.D. Thesis, University of Amsterdam, 1987.

  • P.E. van der Vet, Filosofie van de Scheikunde. Nijhoff, Leiden, 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  • D. van der Waals, Lehrbuch der Thermostatik. Ambrosius Barth, Erster Teil, Leipzig, 1927.

    Google Scholar 

  • B.C. van Frassen, The Scientific Image. Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1980.

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Vasconi, Kant and Lavoisier's Chemistry. In Mosini (Ed.), 1996, pp. 155–162.

  • H.P. Vermeeren, Controversies and Existence Claims in Chemistry: The Theory of Resonance. Synthese 69: 273–290, 1986.

    Google Scholar 

  • R. Vihalemm, Elaboration of Philosophical Problems in Chemistry [in Russian]. Voprosi Filosofii 4(6): 90–95, 187–188, 1974.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Villani, Sostanze e reazioni chimiche: Concetti di chimica teorica di interesse generale. Epistemologia 16: 191–212, 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  • C. Vinti, Bachelard: Ragione e realta nella chimica contemporanea. In Mosini (Ed.), 1996, pp. 181–217.

  • D. von Engelhardt, The Chemical System of Substances, Forces and Processes in Hegel's Philosophy. In R.S. Cohen (Ed.), Hegel and the Sciences. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1984, pp. 41–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • D. von Engelhardt, Philosophie und Theorie der Chemie um 1800. Philosophia Naturalis 23: 223–237, 1986.

    Google Scholar 

  • D. von Engelhardt, Hegel on Chemistry and the Organic Sciences. In M.J. Petry (Ed.), Hegel and Newtonianism. Kluwer, Dordrecht, 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Weatherall, Tarski's Theory of Truth and Field's Solution to the Problem of Intentionality. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71: 291–303, 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  • G.W. Wheland, Resonance in Organic Chemistry. Wiley, New York, NY, 1955.

    Google Scholar 

  • W.R. Woodward and R.S. Cohen, World Views and Scientific Discipline Formation. Kluwer, Dordrecht, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • R.G. Woolley, Must a Molecule Have a Shape? Journal of the American Chemical Society 100: 1073–1078, 1978.

    Google Scholar 

  • R.G. Woolley, Molecular Shapes and Molecular Structure. Chemical Physics Letters 125: 200–205, 1986.

    Google Scholar 

  • R.G. Woolley, Quantum Chemistry Beyond the Born-Oppenheimer Approximation. Journal of Molecular Structure (Theochem) 230: 17–46, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • H. Zandvoort, Models of Scientific Development and the Case of Nuclear Magnetic Resonance. Ph.D. Thesis, University of Groningen, 1985.

  • H. Zandvoort, Macromolecules, Dogmatism, and Scientific Change: The Prehistory of Polymer Chemistry as Testing Ground for Philosophy of Science. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 19: 489–515, 1988.

    Google Scholar 

  • Iu.A. Zhdanov, Homology in Organic Chemistry [in Russian]. Moscow University Press, Moscow, 1950.

    Google Scholar 

  • Iu.A. Zhdanov, Outline of the Methodology of Organic Chemistry [in Russian]. Moscow University Press, Moscow, 1960.

    Google Scholar 

  • Iu.A. Zhdanov, Modelling in Organic Chemistry [in Russian]. Voprosi Filosofii 6: 63–74, 1963.

    Google Scholar 

  • Iu.A. Zhdanov, The Problem of the General Definition of Chemistry. Journal of General Chemistry of the USSR, 2643–2644 [cover to cover translation of Zhurnal Obscei Khimii], 1965.

  • A. Zucker, Davy Refuted Lavoisier not Lakatos. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 39: 537–540, 1988.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

van Brakel, J. On the Neglect of the Philosophy of Chemistry. Foundations of Chemistry 1, 111–174 (1999). https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1009936404830

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1009936404830

Keywords

Navigation