Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

On the Normativity of Intentions

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Suppose you intend now to φ at some future time t. However, when t has come you do not φ. Something has gone wrong. This failing is not just a causal but also a normative failing. This raises the question how to characterize this failing. I discuss three alternative views. On the first view, the fact that you do not execute your intention to φ is blameworthy only if the balance of reasons pointed to φ-ing. The fact that you intended to φ does not add to the reasons for φ-ing at t. On the second view, the fact that you do not execute your intention to φ is blameworthy because you violate a requirement of rationality. Both these views have in common that they deny that intending to φ at t creates a reason to φ at t. The third alternative, the one I defend, claims that you often create reasons to φ by intending to φ.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Bratman (1987, pp. 24–27).

  2. Raz (2005), Brunero (2007), Setiya (2007).

  3. Raz (2005).

  4. Scanlon (1998, p. 18). This does not really help to understand what a reason is as long as we don’t have an account of what a ‘consideration’ is in this context or what it means for such a thing to ‘count in favor of φ-ing’. There are various theoretical positions possible here. There are so-called primitivists about reasons who think that ‘reason’ is a basic concept that defies further analysis (e.g., Scanlon 1998). Others define reasons in terms of the relation they have towards the conclusion of reasoning. For example, (Broome 2004) characterizes the relation ‘… is a reason to …’ as an explanatory one: a reason to φ is (part of) an explanation why one should φ. Kearns and Star (2008) think of this relation as an evidentiary one: a reason to φ is evidence that one should φ. Finally, Schroeter and Schroeter (2009) characterize reasons in terms of the functional relations these bear to the concepts of ‘ought’, ‘right’ and other such normative concepts. In what follows, I do not rely on the accuracy of any of these views.

  5. Many authors make a distinction between normative reasons and motivating reasons (e.g., Smith 1987). The conditions I suggest here for successful deliberation amount to saying that if deliberation is successful then the agent’s motivating reasons are also her normative reasons. Note that this need not be the only condition on the success of a piece of deliberation.

  6. That is, I might be off the hook for not making the phone call, however, it is an open question as to whether my unawareness is a failure.

  7. For similar thoughts, see Holton (2009).

  8. There are more circumstances in which a blameworthy failure of the execution of one’s intention occurs. One could forget one’s decision or one could be weak willed in the sense identified by Holton (1999). In all those cases there is a blameworthy failing that may or may not be reducible to the types of failures mentioned here.

  9. Bratman (1987, 1999, 2007).

  10. Actually, this is too quick. In deliberation we sometimes accept things as ‘given’ even though we do not actually believe them. For example, suppose I have the goal of not getting wet in the rain. Then, in deciding whether to bring an umbrella or put on a raincoat, I take it as given that it will rain and then try to figure out what is better, an umbrella in the rain or a raincoat in the rain. However, I might not be sure that it actually will rain. In the context of my deliberation whether to bring an umbrella or a raincoat, I accept it will rain. My attitude is not belief in the sense of a ‘degrees-of-confidence’ attitude. Neither is it the attitude of ‘full belief’. Instead these attitudes are so-called ‘acceptances’: one takes certain things as ‘given’ in the context of deliberation and decides accordingly. On the other hand, one makes decisions against a background of beliefs about the world. These beliefs are beliefs in both the degrees-of-confidence sense and the full sense—but not the acceptance sense. For example, in deciding whether or not to make that phone call, I do believe that the colleague I try to reach works at the same university as I do. See also, Cohen (1989, 1992), Bratman (1992).

  11. It is remarkably difficult to specify this constraint correctly, compare, for example, Bratman (1981), Broome (1999, 2007), Schroeder (2009).

  12. Commitment, here, is intended in a normative sense. When Ulysses binds himself to the mast so as not to give into the temptation of the Sirens, he is not committed in this sense. However, if Ulysses intends not to give in to the Sirens even though he is tempted, he is committed. See Verbeek (2007a) for a more precise analysis of commitments in this normative sense.

  13. The term ‘myth theory’ in this connection is due to Bratman (2009, 2011). Defenders of myth theory are Raz (2005), Kolodny (2005).

  14. I prefer the expression ‘pro toto’ over ‘all things considered’ that is popular in the literature, because it is not the consideration of reasons that is important but rather the ‘weight’ of all reasons (assuming that the metaphor of ‘weight’ is attractive). ‘All things considered’ suggests that the difference with a pro tanto reason is epistemic, whereas ‘pro toto’ rightly suggests that the difference is metaphysical.

  15. ‘Picking’ as opposed to ‘choosing’ in the way characterized by Ullmann-Margalit and Morgenbesser (1977).

  16. See also Kolodny (2011) for a more complicated answer to the worry.

  17. Raz (2005). Similarly, see Kolodny (2011).

  18. I take this to be the implication of Raz’ ‘facilitative principle’ that roughly says that if there is a reason to pursue an end, there is a reason to pursue the means, and his argument how the ends of the agent can make some reasons normatively salient and others not (Raz 2005).

  19. There are other answers as well, having to do with displaying deliberative virtues, such as resoluteness, and one’s effectiveness as an agent. In what follows I ignore these but my objections to the cost-benefit answer above carry over to this type of answers.

  20. This may be too fast. In the original formulation of the bootstrapping objection, intentions do not provide reasons. If the type of cost-benefit argument mentioned above justifies the inertia of intentions, then this is a case of bootstrapping. Alternatively, one may argue that bootstrapping occurs when the intention to φ is taken as a reason to φ (and not something else). In that case, this would not be a case of bootstrapping, because the inertia of the intention to φ is not justified by the intention to φ, but by the cost-benefit ratio of reconsideration. However, since the change of the cost-benefit ratio of considering whether to φ is due to the formation of the intention to φ, this amounts to some kind of indirect bootstrapping which is alien to the spirit, if not the letter, of myth theory.

  21. However, it is not clear exactly how to distinguish the two (Schroeder 2008, Lord 2010).

  22. Broome (1999, 2001, 2002, 2004, 2005, 2007, 2008, 2009).

  23. However, there may be reasons to comply with requirements or to violate them (Broome 2005).

  24. Broome (1999, p. 403).

  25. For example, Schroeder (2004), Bratman (2007), Kolodny (2007), Reisner (2009), Lord (2010), Way (2010), Brunero (2012).

  26. Harman (1986), Velleman (1989), Setiya (2007) defend the view that these requirements are requirements of theoretical reason; Brunero (2009), Bratman (2011) argue against such ‘cognitivism’; Broome (2009), finally, argues that neither of these extremes is plausible.

  27. I am assuming here that it is straightforward what exactly the requirement of means-end coherence is. However, that is not the case. Poisoning my uncle is but one of the means to avail myself of the inheritance (i.e., it is at best sufficient, not necessary) and things get really tricky once we start thinking of means that are neither necessary nor sufficient (yet causally relevant) for achieving the end.

  28. For a version of this objection, see Setiya (2007). A reply to this objection is in Bratman (2009).

  29. This is, after all, the reason that Broome (2007) and others argue that these requirements are wide-scope.

  30. Foot (1972), Joyce (2006).

  31. E.g., Kolodny (2005).

  32. E.g., Broome (2005).

  33. E.g., Bratman (2009), Holton (2009).

  34. Broome (2005), Bratman (2011). For a defense see Holton (2009).

  35. E.g., Velleman (1992), Bratman (2009). But see Enoch (2006).

  36. Regardless which of these two views one accepts and regardless of how one answers these particular objections, there is the further problem that these considerations are not those one would expect if one takes the distinctions between reasons and requirements on the one hand and narrow- and wide scope on the other seriously. If one insists that the normative pressure of intentions is really normative and at the same time avail oneself of the fact that wide-scoped demands cannot be detached, one would expect that a two-flavor theory would not look for a wide-scope requirement but for a wide-scoped reason of the form that there is a reason to see to it that if one intends the end, one pursue the necessary means.

  37. See also Schroeder (2007).

  38. In what follows, I rely on Verbeek (2007b). A similar, but not identical, view has been developed by den Hartogh (2004). Another version of this idea of authority exercised over oneself is in recent work by Ruth Chang, e.g., Chang (2009).

  39. The notion of authority that follows is roughly that of Joseph Raz’ ‘service conception of authority’ Raz (1985, 1986, 2006), except that it is not committed to the idea that authority comes with exclusionary reasons.

  40. Note that I am using these terms in a technical meaning. The distinction is of course well known from Kant’s distinction between ‘acting in conformity with duty’ and ‘acting out of duty’ (Kant 1785).

  41. Raz (1986).

  42. I abstract here from some of the other ways in which law could be established in some jurisdictions, such as existing conventions or certain types of precedent where no explicit act of parliament is necessary to give it force of law.

  43. Assuming, of course, that the law has authority. This is not a trivial assumption. For a critical discussion, see Simmons (1979).

  44. See for example, Broome (2008), Kearns and Star (2008).

  45. Verbeek (2007a).

  46. Bratman (1987).

  47. den Hartogh (2004).

  48. Or any other fair way—i.e., any way that gives equal weight to A and B—to break the tie between A and B in a fair manner.

References

  • Bratman M (1981) Intention and means-end reasoning. Philos Rev 90:252–265

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman M (1987) Intention, plans, and practical reason. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Bratman M (1992) Practical reasoning and acceptance in a context. Mind 101:1–15

    Google Scholar 

  • Bratman M (1999) Faces of intention: selected essays on intention and agency. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman M (2007) Structures of agency: essays. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman M (2009) Intention, practical rationality, and self-governance. Ethics 119:411–443

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman M (2011) Intention rationality. Philos Explor 12:227–241

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broome J (1999) Normative requirements. Ratio 12:398–419

    Google Scholar 

  • Broome J (2001) Are intentions reasons? And how should we cope with incommensurable values? In: Ripstein A, Morris C (eds) Practical rationality and preference: essays for David Gauthier. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 98–120

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Broome J (2002) Practical reasoning. In: Bermùdez J, Millar A (eds) Reason and nature: essays in the theory of rationality. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 85–112

  • Broome J (2004) Reasons. In: Wallace J, Smith M, Scheffler S, Pettit, P (eds) Reason and value: themes from the moral philosophy of Joseph Raz. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 28–55

  • Broome J (2005) Does rationality give us reasons? Philos Issues 15:321–337

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broome J (2007) Wide or narrow scope. Mind 116:359–370

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broome J (2008) Reply to Southwood, Kearns and Star, and Cullity. Ethics 119:96–108

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broome J (2009) The unity of reasoning? In: Robertson S (ed) Spheres of reason: new essays in the philosophy of normativity. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 62–92

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brunero J (2007) Are intentions reasons? Pac Philos Q 88:424–444

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brunero J (2009) Against cognitivism about practical rationality. Philos Stud 146:311–325

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brunero J (2012) Instrumental rationality, symmetry and scope. Philos Stud 157:125–140

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chang R (2009) Voluntarist reasons and the sources of normativity. In: Sobel D, Wall S (eds) Reasons for action. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 243–271

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen LJ (1989) Belief and acceptance. Mind 98:367–389

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen LJ (1992) An essay on belief and acceptance. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Den Hartogh G (2004) The authority of intention. Ethics 115:6–34

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Enoch D (2006) Agency, shmagency: why normativity won’t come from what is constitutive of action. Philos Rev 115:169–198

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foot P (1972) Morality as a system of hypothetical imperatives. Philos Rev 81:305–316

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman G (1986) Change in view: principles of reasoning. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Holton R (1999) Intention and weakness of will. J Philos 96:241–262

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holton R (2009) Willing, wanting, waiting. Clarendon Press, Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Joyce R (2006) The evolution of morality. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1785) Groundwork for the metaphysics of morals. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kearns S, Star D (2008) Reasons: explanations or evidence? Ethics 119:31–56. doi:10.1086/592587

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kolodny N (2005) Why be rational? Mind 114:509–563

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kolodny N (2007) State or process requirements? Mind 116:371–385

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kolodny N (2011) Aims as reasons. In: Freeman S, Kumar R, Wallace RJ (eds) Reasons and recognition: essays on the philosophy of T.M. Scanlon. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 43–78

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lord E (2010) Having reasons and the factoring account. Philos Stud 149:283–296

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raz J (1985) Authority, law and morality. Monist 68:295–324

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz J (1986) The morality of freedom. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz J (2005) The myth of instrumental rationality. J Ethics Soc Philos 1:1–28

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz J (2006) The problem of authority: revisiting the service conception. Minn Law Rev 90:1003–1044

    Google Scholar 

  • Reisner A (2009) Unifying the requirements of rationality. Philos Explor Int J Philos Mind Action 12:243–260

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon T (1998) What we owe to each other. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder M (2004) The scope of instrumental reason. Philos Perspect 18:337–364

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder M (2007) Slaves of the passions. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder M (2008) Having reasons. Philos Stud 139:57–71

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder M (2009) Means-end coherence, stringency, and subjective reasons. Philos Stud 143:223–248

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeter L, Schroeter F (2009) Reasons as right-makers. Philos Explor 12:279–296

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Setiya K (2007) Cognitivism about instrumental reason. Ethics 117:649–673

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simmons AJ (1979) Moral principles and political obligations. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith M (1987) The Humean theory of motivation. Mind 96:36–61

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ullmann-Margalit E, Morgenbesser S (1977) Picking and choosing. Soc Res 44:757–785

    Google Scholar 

  • Velleman JD (1989) Epistemic freedom. Pac Philos Q 70:73–97

    Google Scholar 

  • Velleman JD (1992) What happens when someone acts. Mind 101:461–481

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Verbeek B (2007a) Rational self-commitment. In: Peter F, Schmid HB (eds) Rationality and commitment. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 150–174

    Google Scholar 

  • Verbeek B (2007b) The authority of norms. Am Philos Q 44:245–258

    Google Scholar 

  • Way J (2010) Defending the wide-scope approach to instrumental reason. Philos Stud 147:213–233

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank John Broome, Markus Schlosser and one anonymous referee, as well as the participants of the First Topoi Conference on ‘Intentions: philosophical and empirical issues’ in Rome, 28–30 November 2012, for their valuable comments. I have benefitted greatly from conversations with Michael Bratman, John Broome, Ruth Chang, and Nic Southwood about these issues over the years.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Bruno Verbeek.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Verbeek, B. On the Normativity of Intentions. Topoi 33, 87–101 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-013-9221-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-013-9221-8

Keywords

Navigation