Skip to main content
Log in

Did nonlinear irreversible thermodynamics revolutionize the classical time conception of physics?

  • Published:
Foundations of Physics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

From both physical and epistemological viewpoints, the following theses, which nowadays are often discussed in the literature, are examined: Nonlinear thermodynamics renders it possible to grasp evolutionary physical processes; for thermodynamics it introduces, instead of idealized reversible time, a directed time into physics; thus a science is established that is nearer to reality than classical physics. To analyze these theses, the relation of thermodynamics to dynamical physics is considered. In particular, it is demonstrated that, in classical as well as in modern thermodynamics, irreversibility is introduced via conditions which must be formulated in addition to the dynamical laws. To show the reason for this, the epistemological status of the physical time conception is analyzed, and its character as a physical measurement quantity is established.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  1. I. Prigogine,Dialektik. Beitr. Phil. Wiss., No. 5, 121 (1982).

  2. L. Boltzmann,Sitz.-Ber. Akad. Wiss. Wien (II)65, 67 (1877).

    Google Scholar 

  3. L. Boltzmann,Ann. Phys. (Leipzig) 57, 773 (1896).

    Google Scholar 

  4. L. Boltzmann,Ann. Phys. (Leipzig) 59, 793 (1896).

    Google Scholar 

  5. M. Planck, “Die Einheit des physikalischen Weltbildes,” and “Physikalische Gesetzlichkeit im Lichte neuerer Forschungen,” inPhysikalische Abhandlungen und Vorträge, Vol. III (F. Vieweg & Sohn, Braunschweig, 1958).

    Google Scholar 

  6. A. Einstein,Phys. Z. 10, 821 (1909).

    Google Scholar 

  7. L. Boltzmann, “Ein Wort der Mathematik an die Energetik,” inPopuläre Schriften (Verlag. Joh. A. Barth, Leipzig, 1905), p. 133.

    Google Scholar 

  8. K. R. Popper,Nature (London) 177, 538 (1956).

    Google Scholar 

  9. K. R. Popper,Nature (London) 178, 382 (1956).

    Google Scholar 

  10. K. R. Popper,Nature (London) 179, 1297 (1957).

    Google Scholar 

  11. K. R. Popper,Nature (London) 181, 402 (1958).

    Google Scholar 

  12. L. Rosenfeld, “Statistical Causality in Atomic Theory. A General Introduction to Irreversibility,” inSelected Papers of Léon Rosenfeld, R. S. Cohen and J. J. Stachel, eds. (D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1979).

    Google Scholar 

  13. L. Boltzmann,Wiener Ber. 66, 275 (1872).

    Google Scholar 

  14. J. Loschmidt,Wiener Ber. 73, 128, 366 (1876).

    Google Scholar 

  15. J. Loschmidt,Wiener Ber. 75, 278 (1877).

    Google Scholar 

  16. J. Loschmidt,Wiener Ber. 76, 209 (1877).

    Google Scholar 

  17. E. Zermelo,Ann. Phys. (Leipzig) 57, 485 (1896).

    Google Scholar 

  18. E. Zermelo,Ann. Phys. (Leipzig) 60, 392 (1897).

    Google Scholar 

  19. P. Ehrenfest and T. Ehrenfest, “Begriffliche Grundlagen der statistischen Auffassung in der Mechanik,” inP. Ehrenfest: Collected Scientific Papers, M. J. Klein, ed. (North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1959), p. 258.

    Google Scholar 

  20. E. Mach,Die Principien der Wärmelehre (F. A. Brockhaus, Leipzig, 1919), p. 338.

    Google Scholar 

  21. H.-J. Treder,Geophys. Veröff. KMU Leipzig 2, 7 (1980).

    Google Scholar 

  22. I. Prigogine,From Being to Becoming—Time and Complexity in Physical Sciences (W. H. Freeman, San Francisco, 1980).

    Google Scholar 

  23. W. Ebeling,Spectrum 12, Nos. 6 and 7 (1981).

  24. N. Bohr and L. Rosenfeld,Kgl. Dan. Vidensk. Selsk. Mat.-fys. Medd. 12, No. 8 (1933).

  25. C. George, I. Prigogine, and L. Rosenfeld, “The Macroscopic Level of Quantum Mechanics,” inSelected Papers of Léon Rosenfeld, R. S. Cohen and J. J. Stachel, eds. (D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1979).

    Google Scholar 

  26. R. Wahsner, “Naturwissenschaft zwischen Verstand und Vernunft,” inVom Mute des Erkennens. Beiträge zur Philosophie G. W. F. Hegels, M. Buhr and T. I. Oiserman, eds. (Akademie Verlag, Berlin, 1981).

    Google Scholar 

  27. H.-H. v. Borzeszkowski and R. Wahsner,Wirkung und Gegenwirkung. Studien zu Bewegung und Widerspruch in der Physik (in press).

  28. K. Marx, “Zur Kritik der politischen Ökonomie,” inWerke, Vol. 13, K. Marx and F. Engels (Dietz Verlag, Berlin, 1961), p. 16.

    Google Scholar 

  29. H. v. Helmholtz,Einleitung zu den Vorlesungen über theoretische Physik, A. König and C. Runge, eds. (Verlag Joh. A. Barth, Leipzig, 1903), p. 26.

    Google Scholar 

  30. K. Marx, “Die Wertform,” inKleine ökonomische Schriften, K. Marx and F. Engels (Dietz Verlag, Berlin, 1955), p. 265.

    Google Scholar 

  31. K. Marx, “Theorien über den Mehrwert,” inWerke, Vol. 26.3, K. Marx and F. Engels (Dietz Verlag, Berlin, 1962), pp. 106–107 and 125.

    Google Scholar 

  32. J. B. d'Alembert,Traité de dynamique, dans lequel les loix de l'équilibre & du mouvement des corps sont réduites au plus petit nombre possible (David, Paris, 1743).

    Google Scholar 

  33. R. Descartes,Regulae ad directionem ingenii, H. Springmeyer, L. Gäbe, and H. Zekl, eds. (Felix Meiner Verlag, Hamburg, 1973), pp. 132–134.

    Google Scholar 

  34. C. Neumann,Über die Principien der Galilei-Newtonschen Theorie (B. G. Teubner, Leipzig, 1870).

    Google Scholar 

  35. L. Lange,Die geschichtliche Entwickelung des Bewegungsbegriffs und ihr voraussichtliches Endergebnis. Ein Beitrag zur historischen Kritik der mechanischen Prinzipien (W. Engelmann, Leipzig, 1886).

    Google Scholar 

  36. E. Cassirer,Substanzbegriff und Funktionsbegriff. Untersuchungen über die Grundfragen der Erkenntniskritik (Bruno Cassirer, Berlin, 1910), p. 192.

    Google Scholar 

  37. H. Poincaré,Rev. Métaphys. Morale 1, 534 (1893).

    Google Scholar 

  38. H.-J. Treder,Große Physiker und ihre Probleme. Studien zur Geschichte der Physik (Akad. Verlag, Berlin, 1983), pp. 179–185.

    Google Scholar 

  39. M. Planck,Wissenschaftliche Selbstbiographie (Verlag Joh. A. Barth. Leipzig, 1955), pp. 54–55.

    Google Scholar 

  40. E. Schrödinger,Die Natur und die Griechen (Zsolnay, Wien, 1955), pp. 94–95 and 155.

    Google Scholar 

  41. E. Schrödinger,Was ist ein Naturgesetz? Beiträge zum naturwissenschaftlichen Weltbild (Oldenbourg, München/Wien, 1962), pp. 33, 56, 62–63, and 72.

    Google Scholar 

  42. G. W. F. Hegel,Differenz des Fichteschen und des Schellingschen Systems der Philosophie (Reclam, Leipzig, 1981), p. 51.

    Google Scholar 

  43. E. Husserl,Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften und die transzendentale Phänomenologie, Husserliana. Ges. Werke, W. Bienel, ed. (Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, 1962), p. 52.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

von Borzeszkowski, HH., Wahsner, R. Did nonlinear irreversible thermodynamics revolutionize the classical time conception of physics?. Found Phys 14, 653–670 (1984). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00738746

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00738746

Keywords

Navigation