Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Compliance and Non-compliance with International Human Rights Standards: Overplaying the Cultural

  • Published:
Human Rights Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper interrogates a ‘positive’ view of culture’s (potential) role in widening compliance with international human rights standards, which (1) concentrates on the ‘cultural’ bases of conflict over rights and, in consequence, (2) focuses primarily on cultural interpretation as a means of achieving greater respect for rights norms. The thrust of the paper is that the relationship between culture and human rights norms is much more complex than this positive perspective implies and, this being so, that some of its claims about the potential benefits of cultural interpretation for widening rights compliance are hard to sustain. I substantiate this argument by exploring five challenges to this approach.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Broadly, the suspicion of bias is grounded in presuppositions concerning the implications of both the origination of rights talk in a Western historical and philosophical context (Powell 1999: 203–206), and the levels of participation in the formulation of existing rights norms. So, for instance, Iris Marion Young observes that ‘those nations and groups in the world today who question the application of existing human rights covenants … argue that the particular formulations of those rights applied today were developed largely by Western powers, and that … these formulations should be subject to review in a process that includes them’ (Young 2000: 271). On this suspicion of bias see also Deborah Weissman (2004).

  2. On cosmopolitan and anti-cosmopolitan arguments, compare the position of John Rawls with those of some of his cosmopolitan critics: Rawls (1999), Thomas Pogge (1994) and Darrel Moellendorf (2002). Within feminism, see Martha Nussbaum (2004, 2005) and Susan Okin (1994, 1998). For communitarian views, see Charles Taylor (1999) and Michael Walzer (1994).

  3. ‘Culture’ is, of course, a contested concept and as such may be defined in a variety of ways. See Abdullahi An-Na’im (An-Na’im 1992: 22–23). I borrow Daniel Bell’s view of cultural tradition as ‘an ongoing argument about the good of the community whose identity it seeks to define’ (Bell 1996: 652, n.31). The idea here is that ‘the cultural traditions of interest to human rights activists…should be living in the sense that fundamental values still have the capacity to motivate action in the contemporary era’ (ibid). It is worthwhile noting that human rights norms might, themselves, be thought of as embodying a specific kind of culture, i.e. ‘human rights culture’. On this view, the relationship between rights and bounded cultures gets recast as a relationship between two kinds of culture; see Richard Rorty (1993). On the relationship between culture and human rights, see Catherine Powell (1999). On the malleability and internal diversity of cultures, see Melville Herskovits (1964) and Roger Keesing (1974). More generally, on the relationship between culture and rights from an anthropological perspective, see Bell et al. (eds) (2001); Cowan et al. (eds) (2001); Mahmood Mamdani (ed.) (2000) and Richard A. Wilson (ed.) (1997).

  4. For empirical literature on the political causes of compliance (and non-compliance) with human rights see Neil J. Mitchell and James M. McCormick (1988); Steven C. Poe and C. Neal Tate (1994); Steven C. Poe et al. (1999) and Abdelaziz Testas (2004).

  5. See Monica Deveaux (2000) and Sally Engle Merry (2005).

  6. On the relationship between Islam and human rights see Janet Afary (2004); Reza Afshari (1994; 2001); Waheeda Amien (2006); Heiner Bielefeldt (1995); Riffat Hassan (1982); Berta Esperanza Hernandez-Truyo (1996); Ann Elizabeth Mayer (1999); Mahmood Monshipouri (1998); Mahmood Monshipouri and Reza Motameni (2000); also, Norani Othman (1999).

  7. For broad ranging discussion on the moral and political implications of intervention see Deen K. Chatterjee and Don E. Scheid (eds) (2003), especially those essays by Stanley Hoffman (2003), Chris Brown (2003), Richard W. Miller (2003), Iris Marion Young (2003) and C. A. J. Coady (2003).

  8. On this, see David Held et al. (2005).

  9. See Charlotte Bunch and Niamh Reilly (1994); and Bunch (1990).

  10. These injustices include sex-selective abortions, female infanticide, dowry burnings, suttee, ‘honour’ killings and prostitution as female slavery (MacKinnon 2006: 194–5). Of course, the accommodation of customs may have both good and bad effects for women, and as such, granting cultural rights as human rights can also have contradictory effects on women’s everyday lives. Women may benefit from the public accommodation of cultural practices because it may make their lives less burdensome; see Alison Dundes Renteln (2005) and Niamh Reilly (2005).

  11. It is important to note the controversy that Nussbaum’s treatment of social criticism has attracted. The suspicion is that her account of internal criticism attempts to impose ‘expertocratic’ knowledge on local contributions by not taking seriously enough the articulation of the ‘voices’ of those oppressed and marginalised women whose situation it seeks to capture (Jaggar 2006; Okin 2003). For instance, Okin observes of Nussbaum’s methodology that ‘whereas Nussbaum aims to enable the…women [in her enquiry] to speak for themselves, and to avoid the error of imposing on them categories that “reflect [her] own immersion in a particular theoretical tradition,” as their interpreter, she has allowed her own voice to dominate’ (Okin 2003: 297). See also Alison Jaggar, who complains that Nussbaum’s approach ‘encourages “us,” the theory builders, to use the ideas of others as evidence or raw data for “our” theories. When “we” are Western philosophers and the others in question are non-philosophers in the Third World, this may come uncomfortably close to treating them as “native informants.”… Rather than recommending genuine consultation with others, this approach recommends that “we” select among others’ expressed preferences in order to appropriate those that “we” endorse for “our” own theoretical and political purposes,’ (Jaggar 2006: 319). Other possible means of dealing with instances of mistaken desires include subjecting participants’ claims in public discourse to a kind of dialogical ‘test’. For Nussbaum’s response to this critique, see (2004b). On the dangers of ‘Western’ feminists ‘speaking for’ oppressed Muslim women, see Lila Abu-Lughod (2006).

  12. Of course this specific challenge to the positive view links to another challenge that many interpretive approaches to justice more generally face, i.e. the question of how to adequately tackle instances of interpretive partiality or the distortion of claims occasioned, in part, by the exercise of power differentials upon public discourse. So, for example, Michael Walzer’s interpretive theory has been critiqued by Rawlsian-liberals for lacking critical external principles that could identify what would count as a ‘reasonable’ interpretation of historical values, see Erin Kelly (2001).

  13. On the notion of the importance of a dialogical approach to justice, see James Tully (2004).

  14. For a discussion of this gap, see David Held and Anthony McGrew (2002: 81ff).

  15. Of course, elites in poor countries also benefit. So, for example, Pogge describes how in poorer countries putschist and tyrannical leaders benefit, at the expense of the poor, from entering their countries into multifarious loan and resource agreements with affluent states (Pogge 2007: 52).

  16. On the link between trade and human rights, see generally Ana Gonzalez-Pelaez (2005); Frederick Abbott et al. (eds) (2006); and, Thomas Cottier et al. (eds) (2005). On the link between trade and human rights in respect of poverty and gender relations see generally Marzia Fontana et al. (1998) and Nilifer Çağatay (2001). For a discussion of the relationship between global structural factors and poverty see Pogge (2004). Though well established, the claim that such a correlation exists still has its critics. For example, according to the neo-liberal view of globalisation this link impacts positively on people’s welfare since the trade transitions required to facilitate the integration of developing countries into the global economy proffer new opportunities for these countries to better protect their members’ rights through increased growth. For empirical work on this link that affirms the neo-liberal view see Julie Harrelson-Stephens and Rhonda Callaway (2003). Yet this neo-liberal view is found wanting. As Cagatay observes, ‘despite the argument that trade liberalization leads to higher growth rates, the evidence is inconclusive’ (Çağatay 2001: 33). Growth cannot tackle the underfulfilment of rights associated with poverty on its own, and experiences of growth may in fact go hand in hand with increased inequality (Tsikata and Kerr 2000: 7, 8). Furthermore, the rate at which poorer countries integrate into the global economy is a significant factor in how well they fare. An ‘excessively fast’ integration, i.e. one which does not allow countries to develop ‘relatively quickly behind protective barriers, before they [have] liberalised their trade’ can tend to leave poorer countries worse off (Held 2005: 12). And yet the institutional economic kingpins of the global order over which rich countries exercise effective control, i.e. the influential international financial institutions, do not tend to favour slow integration. For a comparison of both positions, see David Held and Anthony McGrew (2002).

  17. So, the implication is that, differently structured, international trade policies and rules could be made fairer. It is worth noting that this view finds broad support among those cosmopolitan theories of global justice which seek to arrest the distributive unfairness of the global order through support for the principle of global distributive justice, which underwrites protection for the economic interests of all persons everywhere, regardless of their political or cultural group membership. See Charles Beitz (1999); Moellendorf (2002); and Caney (2005).

  18. While the discussion in this paper is focused specifically on material and cultural factors, as already noted, other factors may be involved in rights violations—political and legal, for example. As such, other hybrid factors also exist such as political–material, political–cultural and so on. For instance, commenting on the case of domestic violence in South Asia, Kamala Visweswaran asks ‘what would it mean to understand [this phenomenon]…and its narrative production, as a product not only of culture, but of state-level policy and the neo-liberal economy?’ (Visweswaran 2004: 511).

  19. The integration of East Asian countries into the global economy illustrates this ambiguity. Compare Yash Ghai (1999) and Kevin Tan (1999).

  20. See Michel Chossudovsky (1995).

  21. This of course is not to say that trade liberalisation can not have more positive outcomes (supra note 16). Rather, the point is that more positive outcomes are more likely to occur when liberalisation is accompanied by other ‘safety net’ measures for the most vulnerable, such as social protection and poverty reduction programmes, as well as some kind of protection for fledging industries (Held 2005: 166).

References

  • Abbott, Frederick M, Christine Breining-Kaufmann and Thomas Cottier (eds). 2006. International Trade and Human Rights: Foundations and Conceptual Issues. University of Michigan Press: Michigan.

  • Abu-Lughod, Lila. 2006. ‘The Muslim Woman’. Eurozine. Available at http://www.eurozine.com.

  • Afary, Janet. 2004. The human rights of Middle Eastern & Muslim women: a project for the 21st century. Human Rights Quarterly 26:106–125.

    Google Scholar 

  • Afshari, Reza. 1994. An essay on Islamic cultural relativism in the discourse of human rights. Human Rights Quarterly 16(2):235–276.

    Google Scholar 

  • Afshari, Reza. 2001. Human Rights in Iran: The Abuse of Cultural Relativism. University of Pennsylvania Press: Philadelphia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ahmed-Ghosh, Huma. 2004. Voices of Afghan: women’s rights, human rights, and culture. Thomas Jefferson Law Review 27:27–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alarcon-Gonzalez, Diana and Terry McKinley. 1999. The adverse effects of structural adjustment on working women in Mexico. Latin American Perspectives 26:103–117.

    Google Scholar 

  • Amien, Waheeda. 2006. Overcoming the conflict between the right to freedom of religion and women’s rights to equality: a South African case study of Muslim marriages. Human Rights Quarterly 28:729–754.

    Google Scholar 

  • An-Na’im, Abdullahi Ahmed. 1987. Religious minorities under Islamic law and the limits of cultural relativism. Human Rights Quarterly 9(1):1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • An-Na’im, Abdullahi Ahmed. 1990. Problems of universal cultural legitimacy. In A. An-Na’im and F. Deng (eds). Human Rights in Africa: Cross-cultural Perspectives. The Brookings Institution: Washington.

    Google Scholar 

  • An-Na’im, Abdullahi Ahmed. 1992. Introduction, Toward a cross-cultural approach to defining international standards of human rights: the meaning of cruel, inhuman, or degrading treatment or punishment, and Conclusion. In A. An-Na’im (ed.). Human Rights in Cross-Cultural Perspectives: A Quest for Consensus. University of Pennsylvania Press: Philadelphia.

    Google Scholar 

  • An-Na’im, Abdullahi Ahmed. 1999. The cultural mediation of human rights: the Al-Arqam case in Malaysia. In J. Bauer and D. Bell (eds). The East Asian Challenge For Human Rights. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • An-Na’im, Abdullahi Ahmed. 2006. Why should Muslims abandon Jihad? Human rights and the future of international law. Third World Quarterly 27(5):785–797.

    Google Scholar 

  • An-Na’im, Abdullahi Ahmed and Deng Francis. 1990. Introduction. In A. An-Na’im and F. Deng (eds). Human Rights in Africa: Cross-Cultural Perspectives. The Brookings Institution: Washington.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arora, Dooly. 1999. Structural adjustment program and gender concerns in India. Journal of Contemporary Asia 29(3):328–361.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bassam, Tibi. 1994. Islamic Law/Shari’a, human rights, universal morality and international relations. Human Rights Quarterly 16(2):277–299.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beitz, Charles. 1999. Political Theory and International Relations. Princeton University Press: Princeton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, Daniel. 1996. The East Asian challenge to human rights: reflections on an east west dialogue. Human Rights Quarterly 18:641–667.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, Daniel. 1998. The limits of liberal justice. Political Theory 26(4):557–582.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, Lynda S., Andrew J. Nathan and Ilan Peleg (eds). 2001. Negotiating Culture and Human Rights. Columbia University Press: New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bielefeldt, Heiner. 1995. Muslim voices in the human rights debate. Human Rights Quarterly 17:587–617.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, Chris. 2003. Selective humanitarianism: in defence of inconsistency. In D. K. Chatterjee and D. E. Scheid (eds). Ethics and Foreign Intervention. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunch, Charlotte. 1990. Women’s rights as human rights: toward a re-vision of human rights. Human Rights Quarterly 12(4):486–498.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunch, Charlotte and Niamh Reilly. 1994. Demanding Accountability: The Global Campaign and Vienna Tribunal for Women’s Human Rights. The Centre for Women’s Global Leadership: New Brunswick.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunch, Charlotte and Susana Fried. 1996. Beijing’95: moving women’s human rights from margin to centre. Signs 22(1):200–204.

    Google Scholar 

  • Çağatay, Nilüfer. 2001. Trade, Gender and Poverty. United Nations Development Programme Report. UNDP: New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Çağatay, Nilüfer. Diane Elson, and Caren Grown. 1995. Introduction. World Development 23(11):1827–1836.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caney, Simon. 2000. Human rights, compatibility and diverse cultures. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 3(1):51–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caney, Simon. 2005. Justice Beyond Borders: A Global Political Theory. Oxford University Press: Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chan, Joseph. 1997. An alternative view: Hong Kong, Singapore, and “Asian Values”. Journal of Democracy 8.2:35–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chan, Joseph. 1999. A Confucian perspective on human rights for contemporary China. In J. Bauer and D. Bell (eds). The East Asian Challenge For Human Rights. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chatterjee, Deen K and D. E. Scheid (eds). 2003. Ethics and Foreign Intervention. CUP: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chossudovsky, Michel. 1995. ‘The World Bank Derogates Women’s Rights’. Third World Resurgence 61/62. available at http://www.twnside.org.sg./title/derog~cn.htm.

  • Coady, C. A. J. 2003. War for humanity: a critique. In D. K. Chatterjee and D. E. Scheid (eds). Ethics and Foreign Intervention. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cottier, Thomas, Joost Pauwelyn and Elisabeth Burgi (eds). 2005. Human Rights and International Trade. OUP: Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cowan, Jane K., Marie-Bénédicte Dembour, and Richard A Wilson (eds). 2001. Culture and Rights: Anthropological Perspectives. CUP: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennis, Suzanna and Elaine Zuckerman. 2006. Gender Guide to World Bank and IMF Policy-Based Lending. Gender Action: Connecticut.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deveaux, Monica. 2000. Conflicting inequalities? Cultural group rights and sexual equality. Political Studies 48:522–539.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Vita, Álvaro. 2007. ‘Inequality and Poverty in Global Perspective’. In T. Pogge (ed.). Freedom From Poverty as a Human Right: Who Owes What to the Very Poor?. Oxford University Press: Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dundes Renteln, Alison. 2005. When rites are rights: cultural challenges to marriage laws. Human Rights Dialogue: An International Forum for Debating Human Rights 2(12):22–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fonchingong, Charles. 1999. Structural adjustment, women, and agriculture in Cameroon. Gender & Development 7(3):73–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fontana, Marzia, Susan Joekes and Rachel Masika. 1998. Global trade expansion and liberalization: gender issues and impacts. Bridge Report No. 42. IDS Brighton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghai, Yash. 1999. Rights, social justice, and globalisation in East Asia. In J. Bauer and D. Bell (eds). The East Asian Challenge For Human Rights. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gonzalez-Pelaez, Ana. 2005. Human Rights and World Trade: Hunger in International Society. Routledge: London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrelson-Stephens, Julie and Rhonda Callaway. 2003. Does trade openness promote security rights in developing countries? Examining the liberal perspective. International Interactions 29(2):143–158.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hassan, Riffat. 1982. On human rights and the Qur’anic perspective. Journal of Ecumenical Studies 19(3):51–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • Held, David. 2005. Globalization: the dangers and the answers and, What are the dangers and the answers? Clashes over globalization. In D. Held et al. Debating Globalization. Polity: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Held, David et al. 2005. Debating Globalisation. Polity: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Held, David and Anthony McGrew. 2002. Globalization/Anti-Globalization. Polity: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hernandez-Truyol, Berta Esperanza. (1996) Women’s rights as human rights: rules, realities and the role of culture: a formula for reform. Journal of International Law 21(3):605–677.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herskovits, Melville J. 1964. Cultural Dynamics. Knopf: New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, Stanley. 2003. Intervention: Should it go on, can it go on?. In D. K. Chatterjee and D. E. Scheid (eds). Ethics and Foreign Intervention. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaggar, Alison. 2005. ‘Saving Amina’: global justice for women and intercultural dialogue. Ethics & International Affairs 19(3):55–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaggar, Alison. 2006. Reasoning about well-being: Nussbaum’s methods of justifying the capabilities. The Journal of Political Philosophy 14(3):301–322.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, Peter. 2000. Human rights and diverse cultures: continuity or discontinuity? Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 3(1):27–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kanji, Nazneen. 1995. Gender, poverty and economic adjustment in Harare, Zimbabwe. Environment and Urbanization 7:37–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keesing, Roger M. 1974. Theories of culture. Annual Review of Anthropology 3:73–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, Erin. 2001. Justice and communitarian identity politics. The Journal of Value Inquiry 35:71–93.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kerr, Joanna. 1999. Markets and women’s international human rights (roundtable discussions). Brooklyn Journal of International Law 25(1):143–147.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindholm, Tore. 1992. Prospects for research on the cultural legitimacy of human rights: the cases of liberalism and Marxism. In A. An-Na’im (ed.). Human Rights in Cross-Cultural Perspectives: A Quest for Consensus. University of Pennsylvania Press: Philadelphia.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacKinnon, Catharine. 2006. Are Women Human? And Other International Dialogues. Belknapp Press: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mamdani, Mahmood. 2000. Beyond Rights Talk and Culture Talk: Comparative Essays on the Politics of Rights and Culture. St Martin’s Press: New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marquette, Catherine M. 1997. Current poverty, structural adjustment, and drought in Zimbabwe. World Development 25(7):1141–l149.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayer, Ann Elizabeth. 1999. Islam and Human Rights: Tradition and Politics. Westview: Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merry, Sally Engle. 2005. Human Rights and Gender Violence: Translating International Law into Local Justice. University of Chicago Press: Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, Richard W. 2003. Respectable oppressors, hypocritical liberators: morality, intervention, and reality. In D. K. Chatterjee and D. E. Scheid (eds). Ethics and Foreign Intervention. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, Neil J. and James M. McCormick. 1988. Economic and political explanations of human rights violations. World Politics 40(4):476–498.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moellendorf, Darrel. 2002. Cosmopolitan Justice. Westview: Boulder.

    Google Scholar 

  • Monshipouri, Mahmood. 1998. Islamism, Secularism, and Human Rights in the Middle East. Rienner: Boulder.

    Google Scholar 

  • Monshipouri, Mahmood. and Reza Motameni. 2000. Globalization, sacred beliefs and defiance: is human rights discourse relevant in the Muslim world? Journal of Church & State 42:709–736.

    Google Scholar 

  • Narayan, Uma. 1997. Dislocating Cultures: Identities, Traditions, and Third World Feminism. Routledge: New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickel, James. 2005. Poverty and rights. The Philosophical Quarterly 55(220):385–402.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha C. 2000. Women and Human Development: The Capabilities Approach. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha C. 2003. Capabilities as fundamental entitlements: Sen and social justice. Feminist Economics 9(2–3):33–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha C. 2004. ‘Women and Theories of Global Justice: Our Need for New Paradigms’. In D. Chatterjee (ed.). The Ethics of Assistance: Morality and the Distant Needy. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha C. 2004b. On hearing women’s voices: a reply to Susan Okin. Philosophy & Public Affairs 32(2):193–205.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha C. 2005. Women’s bodies: violence, security, capabilities. Journal of Human Development 6(2):167–183.

    Google Scholar 

  • Okin Moller, Susan. 1994. Gender inequality and cultural differences. Political Theory 22(1):5–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Okin Moller, Susan. 1998. Feminism, women’s human rights, and cultural differences. Hypatia 13(2):32–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Okin Moller, Susan. 2003. Poverty, well being, and gender: what counts, who’s heard? Philosophy & Public Affairs 31(3):280–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • Othman, Norani. 1999. Grounding human rights arguments in non-western culture: Shari’a and the citizenship rights of women in a modern Islamic State. In J. Bauer and D. Bell (eds). The East Asian Challenge For Human Rights. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poe, Steven C. and C. Neal Tate. 1994. Repression of human rights to personal integrity in the 1980s: a global analysis. The American Political Science Review 88(4):853–872.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poe, Steven C., C. Neal Tate and Linda Camp Keith. 1999. Repression of the human right to personal integrity revisited: a global cross-national study covering the years 1976–1993. International Studies Quarterly 43(2):291–313.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pogge, Thomas. 1994. An egalitarian law of peoples. Philosophy and Public Affairs 23(3):195–224.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pogge, Thomas. 2004. “Assisting” the global poor. In D. Chatterjee (ed). The Ethics of Assistance: Morality and the Distant Needy. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pogge, Thomas. 2007. Severe poverty as a human rights violation. In T. Pogge (ed.). Freedom from Poverty as a Human Right: Who Owes What to the Very Poor?. Oxford University Press: Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Powell, Catherine. 1999. Locating culture, identity, and human rights. Columbia Human Rights Law Review 30:201–224.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1993. Political Liberalism. Columbia University Press: New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1999. The Law of Peoples. Harvard University Press: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reilly, Niamh. 2005. Women’s rights as cultural rights: the case of the Irish travellers. Human Rights Dialogue: An International Forum for Debating Human Rights 2(12):16–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1993. Human rights, rationality, and sentimentality. In S. Shute and S. Hurley (eds). On Human Rights: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures 1993. Basic Books: New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, Richard. 1990. Human rights in an evolving world culture. In A. An-Na’im and F. Deng (eds). Human Rights in Africa: Cross-Cultural Perspectives. The Brookings Institution: Washington.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steans, Jill. 2007. Debating women’s human rights as a universal feminist project: defending women’s human rights as a political tool. Review of International Studies 33: 11–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tan, Kevin. 1999. Economic development, legal reform, and rights in Singapore and Taiwan. In J. Bauer and D. Bell (eds). The East Asian Challenge For Human Rights. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 1999. Conditions of an unforced consensus on human rights. In J. Bauer and D. Bell (eds). The East Asian Challenge For Human Rights. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Testas, Abdelaziz. 2004. Economic and political explanations of Algeria’s human rights violations. The International Journal of Human Rights 8(4):399–411.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsikata, Dzodzi and Joanna Kerr. 2000. Introduction. In Tsikata et al (eds). Demanding Dignity: Women Confronting Economic Reforms in Africa. The North-South Institute: Ottowa.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tully, James. 2004. Recognition and dialogue: the emergence of a new field. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 7(3):84–106.

    Google Scholar 

  • Visweswaran, Kamala. 2004. Gendered states: rethinking culture as a site of South Asian human rights work. Human Rights Quarterly 26:483–511.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walzer, Michael. 1994. Thick and Thin: Moral Argument at Home and Abroad. University of Notre Dame Press: Notre Dame.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weissman, Deborah. 2004. The human rights dilemma: rethinking the humanitarian project. Columbia Human Rights Law Review 35(2):259–336.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whelan, Daniel and Jack Donnelly. 2007. The west, economic and social rights, and the global human rights regime: setting the record straight. Human Rights Quarterly 29:908–949.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, Richard A (ed). 1997. Human rights, culture and context: anthropological perspectives. Pluto: London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, Iris Marion. 1995. Survey article: Rawls’s political liberalism. The Journal of Political Philosophy 3(2):181–190.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, Iris Marion. 2000. Inclusion and Democracy. Oxford University Press: Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, Iris Marion. 2003. Violence against power: critical thoughts on military intervention. In D. K. Chatterjee and D. E. Scheid (eds). Ethics and Foreign Intervention. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am indebted to the IRCHSS (Irish Research Council for the Humanities and Social Sciences) for providing the postdoctoral funding that made this research possible. I am also grateful to John Baker of UCD and the anonymous reviewers of this journal for their helpful comments on an earlier version.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Caroline Walsh.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Walsh, C. Compliance and Non-compliance with International Human Rights Standards: Overplaying the Cultural. Hum Rights Rev 11, 45–64 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12142-008-0107-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12142-008-0107-x

Keywords

Navigation