Skip to main content
Log in

Induction and inference to the best explanation

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I adduce a new argument in support of the claim that IBE is an autonomous (indispensable) form of inference, based on a familiar, yet surprisingly, under-discussed, problem for Hume’s theory of induction. I then use some insights thereby gleaned to argue for the (reductionist) claim that induction is really IBE, and draw some normative conclusions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The D-N model (Hempel 1965, pp. 335–376) is an extreme special case. By deducing the explanandum from initial conditions and a set of laws, we show that it was certain to happen.

  2. Fumerton (1980) shows how some causal inferences can be viewed as inductive ones (by making explicit tacit assumptions). But he doesn’t take up Harman’s detective case challenge, and here, it is not clear how the reduction is to be effected.

  3. Unless otherwise suggested, references to, and quotes from, Hume pertain to the Treatise (1739).

  4. I am here ignoring complications engendered by Goodman’s (1955) new riddle of induction. Let us assume that this is an instance of valid induction.

  5. Hume (1777, p. 113) recognises yet another kind of less auspicious case, in which the observed regularity is perfect, but inadequate for complete confidence in the generalisation. Thus, an Indian prince, who has always lived in a warm climate, is justified in “refus[ing] to believe the first relations concerning the effects of frost [i.e., water freezing]”, but complete certainty that water never freezes would be rash for him. The freezing of water is not “contrary to his experience” or “miraculous”; it is merely “marvelous”, “amazing”, “not conformable to his experience”. He is reasoning—by analogy—about an unfamiliar situation, which imperfectly resembles the one he has experienced. “If you weaken the… resemblance, you weaken the principle of transition, and of consequence that belief, which arises from it” (p. 142).

  6. Can I have an unfelt pain when I am unconscious or asleep? Maybe, but I am assuming that sometimes I am conscious—having eaten the cheese—and do not feel pain in my head.

  7. Moore (1922, pp. 91–2) demurs, implausibly to my mind. “The question whether anything exists, when it is not perceived…seems to me to be one which can only be settled by observation…observation might justify us in concluding that…pains…do not exist, when they are not perceived”.

  8. Fumerton (1980, p. 597) defends the opposite suggestion: that every IBE is, in fact, a case of induction. But his argument is a non sequitur. Even if (contentiously) IBE must be defended by invoking its success in cases where the conclusion is observable and then reasoning inductively to its success tout court, this doesn’t show that IBE does not invoke explanatory considerations that are irreducible to induction.

  9. For Lycan (1988, p. 130), too, simplicity, coherence, fruitfulness and initial plausibility all contribute to the explanatoriness of a hypothesis. Confusingly, Lycan’s list of the features which enhance explanatory goodness (1988, p. 130) includes explanatoriness (in addition to simplicity and fitting what else one already believes). Here, Lycan seems to be using the term ‘explanatoriness’ more narrowly.

  10. In a somewhat similar vein, but in a different context (rebutting the regularity theory of causation), Strawson (1989, p. 30) claims it is absurd that “there is, quite definitely, no reason at all” for the fact that “these massy physical objects…[behave] in perfectly regular ways”. The explanation (to whose truth we may reasonably infer) is that “there definitely is something about the nature of the world given which it is regular” (1989, p. 22).

  11. How are we to construe the claim? According to Lange (2000, p. 111), it means we can only be justified in believing an accidental generalisation if we have checked all the instances. But the accidental generalisation may be very probable even before we check its instances (‘All the people in this room weigh less than 300 lb’, e.g.). Neither does it mean that the probability of the generalisation isn’t increased when an instance is encountered (Goodman 1955), since the positive instance rules out one way in which the generalisation could be false (Lange 2000, p. 113). If P((x)(Ax → Bx)) > 0, then

    P((x)(Ax → Bx)/(Aa^Ba)) > P((x)(Ax → Bx)). The correct explication of the intuition is that a positive instance does not increase the probability of an unexamined case satisfying the generalisation, and doesn’t increase the probability of the generalisation over and above that engendered by eliminating a falsifier (Dretske 1977, p. 256).

  12. We ignore gaps if they can be explained away in a sufficiently simple and plausible manner. IBE also yields an adequate response to Goodman’s riddle. The green and grue hypotheses both explain our experience. But the former is simpler (Hesse 1969).

  13. I take it that Popper’s attempt isn’t successful (Newton-Smith 1981, ch. III).

  14. Ladyman, Douven, Horsten and van Fraassen (1997, p. 316) argue that IBE to the unobservable involves added ontological commitments. Hume (1777, p. 153) argues that “here experience is, and must be entirely silent. The mind has never anything present to it but the perceptions, and cannot possibly reach any experience of their connexion with objects”.

  15. I am persuaded by Weisberg’s (2009) response to van Fraassen’s claim that IBE violates the Bayesian rule of conditionalisation. If, as subjective Bayesians think, any prior probability distribution is permissible, then, to be sure, P(T1/E) may be smaller than P(T2/E) even if T1 better explains E than does T2, and assigning it higher credence in response to E because it better explains it is incompatible with conditionalising. But, Weisberg (2009, p. 137) replies, for an objectivist Bayesian, explanatory considerations constrain permissible conditional probabilities. So if T1 better explains E than does T2, P(T1/E) will be greater than P(T2/E).

References

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1983). What is a law of nature? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Baier, A. C. (1991). A Progress of sentiments. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartelborth, T. (1999). Coherence and explanation. Erkenntnis, 50, 209–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berkeley, G. (1710). Principles of human knowledge. In A. A. Luce and T. E. Jessop (Eds.), The works of Georg Berkeley, 9 vols. (pp. 1948–1957). London: Nelson.

  • Bridgeman, P. W. (1927). The logic of modern physics. New York: MacMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartright, N. (1983). How the laws of physics lie. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Day, T., & Kincaid, H. (1994). Putting inference to the best explanation in its place. Synthese, 98, 271–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dray, W. (1957). Laws and explanation in history. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1977). Laws of nature. Philosophy of Science, 44, 248–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ennis, R. (1968). Enumerative induction and best explanation. Journal of Philosophy, 64, 523–529.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Falkenstein, L., & Welton, D. (2001). Humean contiguity. History of Philosophy Quarterly, 18, 279–296.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feigl, H. (1970). ‘The “orthodox” view of theories’. In M. Radner and S. Winokur (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science. vol. IV, Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

  • Foster, J. (1983). Induction, explanation and natural necessity. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 83, 87–101.

  • Friedman, M. (1974). Explanation and scientific understanding. Journal of Philosophy, 71, 5–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fumerton, R. (1980). Induction and reasoning to the best explanation. Philosophy of Science, 47, 589–600.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gomberg, P. (1976). Coherence and causal inference in Hume’s treatise. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 6, 693–704.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1955). Fact, fiction and forecast. New York: Bobbs-Merrill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1965). The Inference to the best explanation. Philosophical Review, 74, 88–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1968). Enumerative induction as inference to the best explanation. Journal of Philosophy, 64, 529–533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1942). The function of general laws in history. Journal of Philosophy, 39, 35–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C.G. (1965). ‘Aspects of scientific explanation’. In Aspects of scientific explanation. New York: Free.

  • Hesse, M. (1969). Ramifications of grue. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 20, 13–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howson, C. (2000). Hume’s problem. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1739). A treatise of human nature. In: L. A. Selby-Bigge (2nd ed.) (p. 1978). Oxford: Clarendon.

  • Hume, D. (1777). Enquiries concerning human understanding. In: L. A. Selby-Bigge (3rd ed.) (1975). Oxford: Clarendon.

  • Humphreys, P. (1989). The chance of explanation. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1992). Multiple realization and the metaphysics of reduction. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 52, 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1989). Explanatory unification and causal structure. In P. Kitcher & W. C. Salmon (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. XIII). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kneale, W. (1949). Probability and induction. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuipers, T. (2004). ‘Inference to the best theory, rather than inference to the best explanation—kinds of abduction and induction’. In: F. Stadler (Ed.),Induction and deduction in the sciences. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Ladyman, J., Douven, I., Horsten, L., & van Fraassen, B. (1997). A defence of van Fraassen’s critique of abductive inference. Philosophical Quarterly, 47, 305–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2000). Natural laws in scientific practice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K. (1970). ‘Justification, explanation, and induction. In: M. Swain (Ed.). Induction, acceptance, and rational belief. Dordrecht: Reidel.

  • Lewis, D. (1986). ‘Causal explanation’. In: D. Lewis (Ed.). Philosophical papers vol. 2. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Lipton, P. (1991). Inference to the best explanation. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. G. (1988). Judgement, and justification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mendelson, E. (1979). Introduction to mathematical logic (2nd ed.). New York: D. van Nostrand.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, R. W. (1987). Fact and method. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1922). Philosophica studies. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1962). Common-place book (pp. 1919–1953). In: C. Lewy (Ed.). London: Allen–Unwin.

  • Newton-Smith, W. (1981). The rationality of science. London: Routledge–Kegan Paul.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (2004). Truth-seeking by abduction. In F. Stadler (Ed.), Induction and deduction in the sciences. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Okasha, S. (2001). What did hume really show about induction? Philosophical Quarterly, 51, 307–327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1966). ‘Abduction and induction’. In: Collected papers (2nd ed.) Cambridge, MA: Harvard.

  • Popper, K. R. (1972). The logic of scientific discovery (4th ed.). London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, H. H. (1940). Hume’s theory of the external world. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reid, T. (1785). Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man. In: A. D. Woozley (Ed.). London: MacMillan, 1941.

  • Salmon, W. C. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler, I. (1964). The anatomy of inquiry. London: Routledge–Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (1999). Explanation as unification. Synthese, 120, 95–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scriven, M. (1970). Explanation, predictions, and laws. In H. Feigl & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. III). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1988). Confirmation and law-likeness. Philosophical Review, 97, 93–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stebbing, S. (1933). Modern introduction to logic (2nd ed.). London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (1989). The secret connexion: Causation, realism, and David Hume. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (1974). The justification of induction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Weisberg, J. (2009). Locating IBE in the Bayesian framework. Synthese, 167, 125–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ruth Weintraub.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Weintraub, R. Induction and inference to the best explanation. Philos Stud 166, 203–216 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-0034-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-0034-1

Keywords

Navigation