Skip to main content
Log in

On the dangers of making scientific models ontologically independent: taking Richard Levins’ warnings seriously

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Biology and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Levins and Lewontin have contributed significantly to our philosophical understanding of the structures, processes, and purposes of biological mathematical theorizing and modeling. Here I explore their separate and joint pleas to avoid making abstract and ideal scientific models ontologically independent by confusing or conflating our scientific models and the world. I differentiate two views of theorizing and modeling, orthodox and dialectical, in order to examine Levins and Lewontin’s, among others, advocacy of the latter view. I compare the positions of these two views with respect to four points regarding ontological assumptions: (1) the origin of ontological assumptions, (2) the relation of such assumptions to the formal models of the same theory, (3) their use in integrating and negotiating different formal models of distinct theories, and (4) their employment in explanatory activity. Dialectical is here used in both its Hegelian–Marxist sense of opposition and tension between alternative positions and in its Platonic sense of dialogue between advocates of distinct theories. I investigate three case studies, from Levins and Lewontin as well as from a recent paper of mine, that show the relevance and power of the dialectical understanding of theorizing and modeling.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It is beyond the scope of this paper to discuss the related views found in the work of a number of other scholars who also emphasize the importance both of ontological components in our theories and of the process of theorizing as involving an imposition onto nature of those components. See, e.g., Marx Das Kapital v. 1 (Tucker 1978, pp. 320–321); Dewey 1929/1958, 1938 (e.g., 1929/1958, pp. 29–30); Kuhn 1970; Oyama 1985 (e.g., pp. 62–63); Smith 1996 (e.g., pp. 49–50) and Clapin 2002 (e.g., part 5 “On Smith,” pp. 219–292).

  2. One similarity between the two views is that they both accept that the world is categorically complex.

  3. There is some “slop” between the two. For instance, the same formalism can be consistent with different (though almost certainly overlapping) sets of ontological assumptions. I suspect, though, that this is much more common in heavily formalized sciences—especially theoretical physics—than in biology. One of the central unresolved questions of quantum mechanics concerns the interpretation of theory. To what sorts of objects and processes does theory refer? Here, multiple radically different ontological interpretations are consistent with the same formal framework of quantum mechanics. In biology, however, I think that there is a much closer link between formalism and actual (as well as intended) ontological assumptions/ontological interpretation. I am grateful to Marie Svarre Nielsen for discussions on this matter.

  4. I gratefully acknowledge discussions with Faviola Rivera Castro on these points.

  5. See also, e.g., Cartwright (1983, 1999) and Wimsatt (1987).

  6. The word “logos” is also derived from the same Indo-European root “leg-”. Oxford English Dictionary.

  7. This essay originally appeared in Synthese in 1980 (43) and was subsequently reprinted as Chapter 6 of their 1985 book.

  8. Levins and Lewontin mention one more: stochasticity and statistics have been conflated. I will not explore this confusion here.

  9. Their distinction between these terms is admittedly different from mine.

  10. Particularly on the latter point, see Weisberg (2003); see also Odenbaugh (2007).

  11. On robust theorems, Levins writes: “we attempt to treat the same problem with several alternative models each with different simplifications but with a common biological assumption. Then, if these models, despite their different assumptions, lead to similar results we have what we can call a robust theorem which is relatively free of the details of the model. Hence our truth is the intersection of independent lies” (Levins 1966, p. 423). For an analysis of Levins’ notion of robustness, see Wimsatt (1981) and Weisberg (2006).

  12. Recall that their “Dialectics and Reductionism in Ecology” first appeared in 1980.

  13. See Levins (1966, p. 431).

  14. Wade (1992) also provides a useful discussion of precisely these points when he analyzes Fisher’s metaphor of ANOVA methodology and factorial design as a “questionnaire to Nature” (p. 42) which, for a variety of technical reasons including the statistical power of various tests, make one “more likely to discover main effects than... interactions” (p. 43). Now, if the questionnaire is biased in this manner, then users of the questionnaire will, upon receiving answers to their questions, illegitimately attribute properties (e.g., strong main causal effects) to nature that are actually outcomes and artifacts of statistical methodology.

  15. There are clear exceptions to this. Neyman et al. (1956) provides a sophisticated account of the complex interaction among theory, experiments, statistics, and data.

  16. Furthermore, Lewontin articulates this critique in more detail in his “The Analysis of Variance and the Analysis of Causes” [first published by Lewontin (1974); subsequently appeared as Chapter 4 in Levins and Lewontin (1985)], as well as in his 1975 paper co-authored with Marcus Feldman, “The Heritability Hang-Up.”

  17. The title of that chapter is “The Genome as the Unit of Selection.”

  18. Lewontin and White (1960); see also Lewontin and Kojima (1960).

  19. Wade (pers. comm., January 27, 2006) makes this point in a clear manner: “The selection coefficients experienced by particular genes become functions of the frequencies of alleles at other genes or the frequencies of genotypes at other genes when there is epistasis. If you are tracking genotypes, then you might not try bothering to calculate the marginal fitnesses of alleles at specific genes—if you did, you would find that they are functions of allele or genotype frequencies at other loci.”

  20. Winther (2006). For further details please see that article.

  21. Turelli (1994).

  22. Frank (1997, 1998).

  23. See Frank (1998).

  24. I am grateful to my student, Fabrizzio Guerrero McManus, for pointing this out to me.

  25. Recent work in philosophy of science concerning social epistemology could be useful for further development of the ideas expressed in this paper. See, for example, Longino (1993, 2002); Hacking (2002) and Lloyd (2005).

References

  • Cartwright N (1983) How the laws of physics lie. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright N (1989) Nature’s capacities and their measurement. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright N (1999) The dappled world. A study of the boundaries of science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

  • Clapin H (ed.) (2002) Philosophy of mental representation. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK

  • Dewey J (1929/1958) Experience and nature. Dover Publications, Inc, New York

  • Dewey J (1938) Logic. The theory of inquiry. Henry Holt and Co, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Dugatkin LA, Reeve HA (1994) Behavioral ecology and levels of selection: dissolving the group selection controversy. In: Slater PJB et al (eds) Advances in the study of behavior, vol 23. Academic Press, New York, pp 101–133

  • Feldman MW, Lewontin RC (1975) The heritability hang-up. Science 190:1163–1168

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frank S (1997) Cytoplasmic incompatibility and population structure. J Theor Biol 184:327–330

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frank S (1998) Foundations of social evolution. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodnight CJ, Wade MJ (2000) The ongoing synthesis: a reply to Coyne, Barton, and Turelli. Evolution 54:317–324

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking I (2002) Historical ontology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones M (2005) Idealization and abstraction: a framework. In: Jones M, Cartwright N (eds) Idealization XII: correcting the model. Idealization and abstraction in the sciences (Poznan studies in the philosophy of the sciences and the humanities), vol 86. Rodopi, Amsterdam/New York, pp 173–217

  • Kerr B, Godfrey-Smith P (2002) Individualist and multi-level perspectives on selection in structured populations. Biol Philos 17:477–517

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn T (1970) The structure of scientific revolutions, 2nd edn. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Levins R (1966) The strategy of model building in population biology. Am Sci 54:421–431

    Google Scholar 

  • Levins R (1968). Evolution in changing environments. Some theoretical explorations. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Levins R (2005) Living the 11th thesis, paper presented at the meeting of the International Society for the History, Philosophy and Social Studies of Biology, Guelph, Canada

  • Levins R (2006) Strategies of abstraction (this issue)

  • Levins R, Lewontin RC (1985) The dialectical biologist. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC (1974) The genetic basis of evolutionary change. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC, Kojima K (1960) The evolutionary dynamics of complex polymorphisms. Evolution 14:458–472

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC, White MJD (1960) Interaction between inversion polymorphisms of two chromosome pairs in the Grasshopper, Moraba scurra. Evolution 14:116–129

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd EA (2005) The case of the female orgasm. Bias in the science of evolution. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino H (1993) Subjects, power, and knowledge: description and prescription in feminist philosophies of science. In: Alcoff L, Potter E (eds) Feminist epistemologies. Routledge, London, pp 101–120

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino H (2002) The fate of knowledge. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Neyman J, Park T, Scott EL (1956) Struggle for existence. The Tribolium model: biological and statistical aspects. In: Neyman J (ed.) Proceedings of the third berkeley symposium on mathematical statistics and probability, vol 4. University of California Press, Berkeley, pp 41–79

  • Odenbaugh J (2007) Idealized, inaccurate, and successful: a pragmatic approach to evaluating models in theoretical ecology. Biol Philos (forthcoming)

  • Ollman B (2003) Dance of the dialectic. Steps in Marx’s method. University of Illinois Press, Champaign, IL

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyama S (1985) The ontogeny of information. Developmental systems and evolution. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK Reprinted by Duke University Press, 2000

  • Smith BC (1996) On the origin of objects. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K (1996) The return of the group. Philos Sci 63:562–584

    Google Scholar 

  • Tucker RC (1978) The Marx-Engels reader, 2nd edn. WW Norton & Co, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Turelli M (1994) Evolution of incompatibility-inducing microbes and their hosts. Evolution 48:1500–1513

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wade MJ (1992) Sewall Wright: gene interaction and the Shifting Balance Theory. In: Futuyma D, Antonovics J (eds) Oxford surveys in evolutionary biology, vol 8. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK, pp 35–62

  • Weisberg M (2003) When less is more: Tradeoffs and idealization in model building. Doctoral Dissertation, Stanford University

  • Weisberg M (2006) Robustness analysis. Philosophy of Science 73(5)

  • Williams GC (1966) Adaptation and natural selection. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

  • Wilson RA (2003) Pluralism, entwinement, and the levels of selection. Philos Sci 70:531–552

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt WC (1980) Reductionistic research strategies and their biases in the units of selection controversy. In: Nickles T (ed.) Scientific discoveries: case studies. Reidel, Dordrecht, Netherlands, pp 213–259

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt WC (1981) Robustness, reliability and overdetermination. In: Brewer T, Collins B (eds) Scientific inquiry and the social sciences. Jossey-Bass, San Francisco, pp 124–163

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt WC (1986) Forms of aggregativity. In: Donogan A, Perovich N Jr, Wedin M (eds) Human nature and natural knowledge. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Netherlands, pp 259–291

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt WC (1987) False models as means to truer theory. In: Nitecki MH, Hoffman A (eds) Neutral models in biology. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK, pp 23–55

    Google Scholar 

  • Winther RG (2006) Fisherian and Wrightian perspectives in evolutionary genetics and model-mediated imposition of theoretical assumptions. J Theor Biol 240:218–232

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright S (1959) Physiological genetics, ecology of populations, and natural selection. Perspect Biol Med 3:107–151

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright S (1969) Evolution and the genetics of populations, vol 2. The theory of gene frequencies. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am particularly grateful to Michael Weisberg for his comments and advice on this paper and for editing this issue of Biology and Philosophy. I thank Eduardo García Ramírez, Richard Levins, Fabricio Guerrero McManus, Sergio Martínez, Susan Oyama, Faviola Rivera Castro, Marie Svarre Nielsen, David Teira, Francisco Vergara-Silva, and Michael Wade for extremely useful comments on earlier drafts of this paper. I appreciate numerous discussions with Claus Emmeche, Peter Godfrey-Smith, Paul Griffiths, Elisabeth Lloyd, and Robert A. Wilson concerning issues pertinent to this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Rasmus Grønfeldt Winther.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Winther, R.G. On the dangers of making scientific models ontologically independent: taking Richard Levins’ warnings seriously. Biol Philos 21, 703–724 (2006). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-006-9053-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-006-9053-7

Keywords

Navigation