Skip to main content
Log in

The Future of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I examine the value and limitations of Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions. In the interests of developing a social epistemology of science, I argue that we should draw on Kuhn’s later work, published in The Road since Structure. There, Kuhn draws attention to the important role that specialty formation plays in resolving crises in science, a topic he did not discuss in Structure. I argue that we need to develop a better understanding of specialty research communities. Kuhn’s later work provides a research agenda for those who want to study scientific specialization. I briefly discuss some recent studies that promise to provide valuable insight into the social structure of science.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The term “paradigm” was used by others before Kuhn, as David Cedarbaum (1983) recounts. On the ultimate fate of the concept of paradigm in Kuhn’s philosophy see Wray (2011, Chapter 3). Contemporary with Kuhn’s use of the term “incommensurability” was Paul Feyerabend’s use of the term (see Feyerabend 1962). They were colleagues at the time, and Kuhn got feedback on an early draft of Structure from Feyerabend. Normal science, though, was original with Kuhn.

  2. Marx and Bornmann (2010) report on the increasing use of the term “paradigm” in the titles of scientific articles. 1,372 articles published in 2008 in journals indexed in Web of Science had paradigm in the title. Only 8 articles published in 1961 had the term in the title.

  3. Alexander Bird (2000) regards this dimension of Kuhn’s work as his key constructive contribution to philosophy of science. Indeed, philosophy of science is now so thoroughly naturalized that it can be challenging to imagine what philosophy of science was like before this turn.

  4. Kuhn, though, changed his view on the relevance of the history of science to the philosophy of science (see Kuhn 2000a; and Wray 2011, Chapter 5). He later encouraged philosophers to adopt a historical perspective on science, that is, an evolutionary perspective. This is the key insight philosophers can learn from historians. Thus, the focus was no longer on using the history of science as a source of data to constrain our theorizing about science. There has been some debate about what role history can play in philosophy of science. On the one hand, it seems obvious that one cannot generalize from a case or two (Pitt 2001). But, on the other hand, an examination of case studies has led us to ask different questions about science, which in turn has enhanced our understanding of science and scientific change (see Burian 2001).

  5. Kuhn thought that sociology was relevant to his project, but he envisaged sociologists helping us understand the social structure of research communities (see Kuhn 1962, 176–181). He thus did not anticipate the rise of the Strong Programme, which would cause him such grief later as he tried to distinguish his own view from their view (see Kuhn 2000a; and Wray 2011, Chapter 9).

  6. According to Kuhn’s mature view of paradigms, it seems that the social sciences could have them. According to his mature view, a paradigm is an exemplar, a concrete solution to a scientific problem that provides a template for solving other related problems (see Kuhn 1974, Chapter 12; Wray 2011, Chapter 3). Margaret Masterman’s (1970) famous paradigm paper played a crucial role in helping Kuhn clarify his own understanding of paradigms. Kuhn came to believe that even before a consensus emerges in a field, scientists may work with a variety of paradigms (see Kuhn 2000c, 167-68, and 2000d, 300). Recently, Shiping Tang (2011) identified 11 “foundational paradigms” in the social sciences. According to Tang (2011) different paradigms “shed light on different aspects of human society, but each … can only shed light on a limited area of human society” (211).

  7. I have defended Kuhn against the charge of constructionism elsewhere (see Wray 2011, Chapter 9). I argue that some forms of constructionism are less threatening than Kuhn’s critics suggest, and that Kuhn’s constructionism is not as radical as the constructionism of the Strong Programme.

  8. Kristina Rolin (2002) also discusses the role of trust in science. Rolin raises the concern that scientists’ judgments of their colleagues’ trustworthiness may not map onto their trustworthiness reliably. She is especially concerned that this may affect the way reports by female scientists are received.

  9. Kuhn’s appreciation of the role of fruitfulness in theory evaluation was derived, in part, from working with J. B. Conant on the General Education Science courses at Harvard (see Swerdlow 2004, 70). It was already an important theme in Kuhn’s Copernican Revolution (see Kuhn 1957, 41).

References

  • Bird A (2000) Thomas Kuhn. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Burian RM (2001) The dilemma of case studies resolved: the virtues of using case studies in the history and philosophy of science. Perspect Sci Hist Philos Soc 9(4):383–404

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cedarbaum DG (1983) Paradigms. Stud Hist Philos Sci 14(3):173–213

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Langhe R (2010) The division of labour in science: the tradeoff between specialization and diversity. J Econ Methodol 17(1):37–51

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eckberg DL, Hill L Jr (1979) The paradigm concept and sociology: a critical review. Am Sociol Rev 44:925–937

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend P (1962) Explanation, reduction, and empiricism. In: Feigl H, Maxwell G (eds) Scientific explanation, space, and time, Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, vol 3. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller S (2000) Thomas Kuhn: a philosophical history for our times. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Grandy RE (2003) Kuhn’s world changes. In: Nickles T (ed) Thomas Kuhn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Haack S (2003) Defending science—within reason: between scientism and cynicism. Prometheus Books, Amherst

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardwig J (1991) The role of trust in knowledge. J Philos LXXXVIII:693–708

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (1993) The advancement of science: science without legend, objectivity without illusion. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Koertge N (ed) (1998) A house built on sand: exposing postmodern myths about science. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn TS (1957) The Copernican Revolution: planetary astronomy in the development of western thought. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn TS (1962/1996) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 3rd edn. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Kuhn TS (1974/1977) Second thoughts on paradigms. In Kuhn TS (ed) The essential tension: selected studies in scientific tradition and change. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Kuhn TS (2000a) The trouble with the historical philosophy of science. In: Conant J, Haugeland J (eds) The road since structure: philosophical essays, 1970–1993, with an autobiographical interview. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Kuhn TS (2000b) Possible worlds in the history of science. In: Conant J, Haugeland J (eds) The road since structure: philosophical essays, 1970–1993, with an autobiographical interview. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Kuhn TS (2000c) Reflections on my critics. In: Conant J, Haugeland J (eds) The road since structure: philosophical essays, 1970–1993, with an autobiographical interview. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Kuhn TS (2000d) A discussion with Thomas S. Kuhn. In: Conant J, Haugeland J (eds) The road since structure: philosophical essays, 1970–1993, with an autobiographical interview. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Kuhn TS (2000e) The road since structure. In: Conant J, Haugeland J (eds) The road since structure: philosophical essays, 1970–1993, with an autobiographical interview. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Lakatos I (1970) Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In: Lakatos I, Musgrave A (eds) Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Proceedings of the international colloquium in the philosophy of science, London, 1965, vol 4. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

  • Marx W, Bornmann L (2010) How accurately does Thomas Kuhn’s Model of paradigm change describe the transition from the static view of the universe to the big bang theory in cosmology. Scientometrics 82(2):441–464

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Masterman M (1970) The nature of a paradigm. In: Lakatos I, Musgrave A (eds) Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge: Proceedings of the International Colloquium in the Philosophy of Science, London, 1965, Volume 4. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Pitt JC (2001) The dilemma of case studies: toward a Heraclitian philosophy of science. Perspect Sci Hist Philos Soc 9(4):373–382

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rolin K (2002) Gender and trust in science. Hypatia 17(4):95–120

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stove DC (1982) Popper and after: four modern irrationalists. Pergamon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Swerdlow NM (2004) An essay on Thomas Kuhn’s first scientific revolution, The Copernican Revolution. Proc Am Philos Soc 148(1):64–120

    Google Scholar 

  • Tang S (2011) Foundational paradigms of social sciences. Philos Soc Sci 41:211–249

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg S (1998) The revolution that didn’t happen. New York Rev Books 45(15):48–52

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolin S (1968) Paradigms and political theories. In King P, Parekh BC (eds) Politics and experience. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

  • Wray KB (2011) Kuhn’s evolutionary social epistemology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zollman KJS (2007) The Communication Structure of Epistemic Communities. Philos Sci 74(5):574–587

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank Lori Nash and the guest editor for this special issue, Rogier De Langhe, for constructive feedback on this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to K. Brad Wray.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Wray, K.B. The Future of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions . Topoi 32, 75–79 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-012-9140-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-012-9140-0

Keywords

Navigation