Skip to main content
Log in

The Higgs discovery as a diagnostic causal inference

  • S.I.: Evidence for the Higgs Particle
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I reconstruct the discovery of the Higgs boson by the ATLAS collaboration at CERN as the application of a series of inferences from effects to causes. I show to what extent such diagnostic causal inferences can be based on well established knowledge gained in previous experiments. To this extent, causal reasoning can be used to infer the existence of entities, rather than just causal relationships between them. The resulting account relies on the principle of causality, attributes only a heuristic role to the theory’s predictions, and shows how, and to what extent, data selection can be used to exclude alternative causes, even “unconceived” ones.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Cf. Arabatzis (2012, Sect. 9.2) for the difficulty of choosing an adequate term.

  2. Here and in the remainder of the article, I use statements about the probability of instantiations of event types given the instantiation of certain other event types, and statements about the probability of the former instantiations being caused by the latter as equivalent. I take it that the way regularity theories of causation deal with causal relations between token events (rather than between event types) justifies this equivalence (cf. Baumgartner 2013).

  3. For a study of the case of the discovery and detection of the W boson, which includes some unpublished material and defends a similar thesis as the one proposed here, see Wüthrich (2012).

  4. Often, “electron” (e) and “muon” (\(\mu \)) is used to refer to either the particle or the anti-particle, i.e. positron or anti-muon. They have the same “flavour” but opposite charge (see, for instance, ATLAS Collaboration 2012, p. 3).

  5. “Electron [or positron] candidates must have a well-reconstructed [inner detector] track pointing to an electromagnetic calorimeter cluster and the cluster should satisfy a set of identification criteria [...]” (ATLAS Collaboration 2012, p. 3).

  6. This point was brought to my attention by Markus Zinser.

  7. For a virtual particle, the usual relation between the rest mass, the energy and the momentum of a particle is not satisfied.

  8. It is custom among physicists to assume that interference effects in this kind of analysis are negligible (see, e.g., Sjöstrand et al. 2006, p. 10). The assumption seems to be warranted in the present case (see ATLAS Collaboration 2012, p. 5, and reference therein to the preprint of Kauer and Passarino 2012).

  9. “This observation [...] is compatible with the production and decay of the Standard Model Higgs boson” (ATLAS Collaboration 2012, p. 1).

  10. Note that the terminology I use here is different from the one often used in the context of quantum field theory where the term “causality” denotes versions of this latter “locality” assumption. Also, as indicated at the beginning of Sect. 2, I distinguish between “causality” and “determinism”.

  11. For instance, they still speak of the “newly observed particle” (ATLAS Collaboration 2013, p. 88), and of “the discovery of a new particle” (ATLAS Collaboration 2014, p. 234), rather than of the (Standard Model’s) Higgs boson, in the introductions to their papers. See also footnote 9.

References

  • Arabatzis, T. (2012). Hidden entities and experimental practice. In S. Mauskopf & T. Schmalz (Eds.), Integrating history and philosophy of science: Problems and prospects (pp. 125–139). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • ATLAS Collaboration (2012). Observation of a new particle in the search for the Standard Model Higgs boson with the ATLAS detector at the LHC. Physics Letters B, 716, 1–29.

  • ATLAS Collaboration (2013). Measurements of Higgs boson production and couplings in diboson final states with the ATLAS detector at the LHC. Physics Letters B, 726, 88–119.

  • ATLAS Collaboration (2014). Fiducial and differential cross sections of Higgs boson production measured in the four-lepton decay channel in pp collisions at with the ATLAS detector. Physics Letters B, 738, 234–253.

  • Baumgartner, M. (2008). Regularity theories reassessed. Philosophia, 36, 327–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumgartner, M. (2009). Uncovering deterministic causal structures: A Boolean approach. Synthese, 170, 71–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumgartner, M. (2013). A regularity theoretic approach to actual causation. Erkenntnis, 78(1), 85–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumgartner, M., & Graßhoff, G. (2004). Kausalität und kausales Schliessen. Eine Einführung mit interaktiven Übungen. Bern: Bern Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science.

  • Bell, J. S. (1964). On the Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen paradox. Physics, 1(3), 195–200.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohm, D. (1952a). A suggested interpretation of the quantum theory in terms of “hidden” variables. I. Physical Review, 85(2), 166–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bohm, D. (1952b). A suggested interpretation of the quantum theory in terms of “hidden” variables. II. Physical Review, 85(2), 180–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1983). How the laws of physics lie. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • CMS Collaboration (2012). Observation of a new boson at a mass of 125 GeV with the CMS experiment at the LHC. Physics Letters B, 716(1), 30–61.

  • Egg, M. (2012). Causal warrant for realism about particle physics. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 43(2), 259–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, A. (1998). Selectivity and the production of experimental results. Archive for History of Exact Sciences, 53(5), 399–485.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graßhoff, G., & May, M. (2001). Causal regularities. In W. Spohn, M. Ledwig, & M. Esfeld (Eds.), Current issues in causation (pp. 85–114). Paderborn: Mentis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graßhoff, G., & May, M. (2003). Hans Krebs and Kurt Henseleit’s laboratory notebooks and their discovery of the urea cycle: Reconstructed with computer models. In F. Holmes, J. Renn, & H. J. Rheinberger (Eds.), Reworking the bench: Research notebooks in the history of science (pp. 269–294). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. (1966). Philosophy of natural science. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauer, N., & Passarino, G. (2012). Inadequacy of zero-width approximation for a light Higgs boson signal. Journal of High Energy Physics, 2012(8), 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the best explanation (2nd ed.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. (2011). Quantum non-locality and relativity: Metaphysical intimations of modern physics. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nickelsen, K., & Graßhoff, G. (2011). In pursuit of formaldehyde: Causally explanatory models and falsification. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 42(3), 297–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rappaport, S. (1996). Inference to the best explanation: Is it really different from Mill’s methods? Philosophy of Science, 63, 65–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scholl, R. (2015). Inference to the best explanation in the catch-22: How much autonomy for Mill’s method of difference? European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 5(1), 89–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sjöstrand, T., Mrenna, S., & Skands, P. (2006). PYTHIA 6.4 physics and manual. Journal of High Energy Physics, 2006(05), Article 026.

  • Spirtes, P., Glymour, C. N., & Scheines, R. (1993). Causation, prediction, and search. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Staley, K. (2004). The evidence for the top quark: Objectivity and bias in collaborative experimentation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, P. K. (2006). Exceeding our grasp: Science, history, and the problem of unconceived alternatives. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2008). Experimental realism reconsidered: How inference to the most likely cause might be sound. In S. Hartmann, C. Hoefer, & L. Bovens (Eds.), Nancy Cartwright’s philosophy of science (pp. 137–163). New York: Routledge.

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1982). The Charybdis of realism: Epistemological implications of Bell’s inequality. Synthese, 52, 25–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wüthrich, A. (2012). Methoden des Nachweises von Elementarteilchen: Die (Wieder-)Entdeckung des W-Bosons 1983 und 2010. In G. Graßhoff, & A. Wüthrich (Eds.), MetaATLAS: Studien zur Generierung, Validierung und Kommunikation von Wissen in einer modernen Forschungskollaboration (pp. 215–264). Bern: Bern Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science.

  • Wüthrich, A. (2014). Local acausality. Foundations of Physics, 44(6), 594–609.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Work for this article has been funded by the Swiss National Science Foundation (grant no. 145409), and has been carried out at the Centre for Philosophy of Natural and Social Science of the London School of Economics and Political Science, the Max Planck Institute for the History of Science, and at my home institution, the Technical University Berlin. The central ideas presented here originated in discussions at the history and philosophy of science unit at the University of Bern, in particular within the “MetaATLAS” group consisting of Gerd Graßhoff, Basil Marti, Maya Schefer, and me. I also thank Hans Peter Beck for valuable discussions, and the two reviewers for their detailed and constructive comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Adrian Wüthrich.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Wüthrich, A. The Higgs discovery as a diagnostic causal inference. Synthese 194, 461–476 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0941-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0941-8

Keywords

Navigation