Skip to main content
Log in

Twenty-five basic theorems in situation and world theory

  • Published:
Journal of Philosophical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Conclusion

The foregoing set of theorems forms an effective foundation for the theory of situations and worlds. All twenty-five theorems seem to be basic, reasonable principles that structure the domains of properties, relations, states of affairs, situations, and worlds in true and philosophically interesting ways. They resolve 15 of the 19 choice points defined in Barwise (1989) (see Notes 22, 27, 31, 32, 35, 36, 39, 43, and 45). Moreover, important axioms and principles stipulated by situation theorists are derived (see Notes 33, 37, and 38). This is convincing evidence that the foregoing constitutes a theory of situations. Note that worlds are just a special kind of situation, and that the basic theorems of world theory, which were derived in previous work, can still be derived in this situation-theoretic setting. So there seems to be no fundamental incompatibility between situations and worlds — they may peacably coexist in the foundations of metaphysics. The theory may therefore reconcile two research programs that appeared to be heading off in different directions. And we must remind the reader that the general metaphysical principles underlying our theory were not designed with the application to situation theory in mind. This suggests that the general theory and the underlying distinction have explanatory power, for they seem to relate and systematize apparently unrelated phenomena.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Bibliography

  • Aczel, P., 1988,Non-Weil-Founded Sets, CSLI Lecture Notes, No. 14, Stanford: Center for the Study of Language and Information Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adams, R. M., 1974, “Theories of Actuality,”Nous 8: 211–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adams, R. M., 1981, “Actualism and Thisness,”Synthese 49: 3–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, C. A., 1984, “General Intensional Logic,” inHandbook of Philosophical Logic, Vol. II, D. Gabbay and F. Guenthner (eds.), Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 355–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J., 1985, “The Situation in Logic — III: Situations, Sets, and the Axiom of Foundation,” Technical Report No. CSLI-85-26, Stanford: Center for the Study of Language and Information Publications; page references are to the reprint in Barwise (1989).

    Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J., 1989,The Situation in Logic, CSLI Lecture Notes, No. 17, Stanford: Center for the Study of Language and Information Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J. and Perry, J., 1980, “The Situation Underground,” inStanford Working Papers in Semantics, J. Barwise and I. Sag (eds.), Stanford Cognitive Science Group.

  • Barwise, J. and Perry, J., 1981a, “Semantic Innocence and Uncompromising Situations,” inMidwest Studies in Philosophy: 6, P. French, T. Uehling, and H. Wettstein (eds.), Minneapolis: University of Minnesota, 387–404.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J. and Perry, J., 1981b, “Situations and Attitudes,”Journal of Philosophy 78/11: 668–691.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J. and Perry, J., 1983,Situations and Attitudes, Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J. and Perry, J., 1984, “Shifting Situations and Shaken Attitudes,” Technical Report No. CSLI-84-13, Stanford: Center for the Study of Language and Information Publications; also published inLinguistics and Philosophy 8/1 (1985): 105–61 (all page references are to the 1984 publication).

    Google Scholar 

  • Castañeda, H. N., 1974, “Thinking and the Structure of the World,”Philosophia 4: 3–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R., 1976,Person and Object, La Salle: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cresswell, M., 1973,Logics and Languages, London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Church, A., 1951, “A Formulation of the Logic of Sense and Denotation,”Structure, Method, and Meaning, New York: The Liberal Arts Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deutsch, H., 1990, “Contingency and Modal Logic,”Philosophical Studies 60: 89–102.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K., 1977, “Postscript” to Arthur Prior,Worlds, Times, and Selves, Amherst: University of Massachusetts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K., 1985, “Plantinga on the Reduction of Possibilist Discourse,” inAlvin Plantinga, J. Tomberlin and P. van Inwagen (eds.), Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G., 1892, “On Sense and Reference,” inTranslations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, P. Geach and M. Black (ed.), Oxford: Blackwell, 1970, 56–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D., 1977, “Demonstratives,” inThemes from Kaplan, J. Almog, H. Wettstein, and J. Perry (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989, 481–563.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S., 1963, “Semantical Considerations on Modal Logic,”Acta Philosophica Fennica 16: 83–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S., 1959, “A Completeness Theorem in Modal Logic,”Journal of Symbolic Logic 24: 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D., 1986,On the Plurality of Worlds, Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D., 1973, “Possible Worlds,” inCounterfactuals, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, pp. 84–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W., 1988, “Review ofOn the Plurality of Worlds,”The Journal of Philosophy 85 (January): 42–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mally, E., 1912,Gegenstandstheoretische Grundlagen der Logik und Logistik, Leipzig: Barth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meinong, A., 1904, “Über Gegenstandstheorie,” in A. Meinong (ed.),Untersuchungen zur Gegenstandstheorie und Psychologie, Leipzig: Barth; English translation, “On the Theory of Objects,” inRealism and the Background of Phenomenology, R. Chisholm (ed.), Glencoe: The Free Press, 1960, 76–117.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menzel, C., 1991, ‘The True Modal Logic,”Journal of Philosophical Logic 20: 331–374.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague, R., 1974,Formal Philosophy, R. Thomason (ed.), New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Myhill, J., 1963, “An Alternative to the Method of Extension and Intension,” inThe Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, P. Schilpp (ed.), La Salle: Open Court, 299–310.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J., 1986, “From Worlds to Situations,”Journal of Philosophical Logic 15: 83–107.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A., 1974,The Nature of Necessity, Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A., 1976, “Actualism and Possible Worlds,”Theoria 42: 139–60.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J., 1984,The Foundations of Philosophical Semantics, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O., 1960, “Variables Explained Away,” reprinted inSelected Logic Papers, New York: Random House, 227–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rapaport, W., 1978, “Meinongian Theories and a Russellian Paradox,”Nous 12: 153–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E., 1986, “Imagery and Imagination — Sensory Images and Fictional Characters,” inGrazer Philosophische Studien, R. Haller (ed.),25/26: 485–500.

  • Stalnaker, R., 1986a, “Possible Worlds and Situations,”Journal of Philosophical Logic 15: 109–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R., 1986b, “Counterparts and Identity,” inMidwest Studies in Philosophy, XI, P. French, T. Uehling, and H. Wettstein (eds.), Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 121–140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R., 1985,Inquiry, Cambridge: Bradford/MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R., 1976, “Possible Worlds,”Nous 10: 65–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, P., 1986, “Two Concepts of Possible Worlds,” inMidwest Studies in Philosophy, XI, P. French, T. Uehling, and H. Wettstein (eds.), Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 185–213.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zalta, E., 1991, “A Theory of Situations,” inSituation Theory and Its Applications, II, J. Barwise, G. Plotkin, and S. Tutiya (eds.), Stanford: Center for the Study of Language and Information Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zalta, E., 1988,Intensional Logic and the Metaphysics of Intentionality, Cambridge: MIT Press/Bradford Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zalta, E., 1987, “On the Structural Similarities between Worlds and Times,”Philosophical Studies 51: 213–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zalta, E., 1983,Abstract Objects: An Introduction to Axiomatic Metaphysics, Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Additional information

This research was conducted at the Center for the Study of Language and Information (CSLI). I would like to thank John Perry for generously supporting my research both at CSLI and in the Philosophy Department at Stanford. I would also like to thank Bernard Linsky, Chris Menzel, Harry Deutsch and Tony Anderson for many worthwhile and interesting suggestions for improving the paper. An earlier version of the paper, more narrowly focused on situation theory, has appeared in Zalta (1991).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Zalta, E.N. Twenty-five basic theorems in situation and world theory. J Philos Logic 22, 385–428 (1993). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01052533

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01052533

Keywords

Navigation