The Liberal Value of Privacy

Law and Philosophy 29 (5):505-534 (2010)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

This paper presents an argument for the value of privacy that is based on a purely negative concept of freedom only. I show that privacy invasions may decrease a person’s negative freedom as well as a person’s knowledge about the negative freedom she possesses. I argue that not only invasions that lead to actual interference, but also invasions that lead to potential interference (many cases of identity theft) constitute actual harm to the invadee’s liberty interests, and I critically examine the courts’ reliance on a principle of ‘no harm, no foul’ in recent data breach cases. Using a number of insights from the psychology of human belief, I also show that the liberal claim for protection of privacy is strengthened by the observation that often the privacy invader cannot be held responsible for the influence on the invadee’s negative freedom.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,349

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Liberal and communitarian defenses of workplace privacy.Rita C. Manning - 1997 - Journal of Business Ethics 16 (8):817-823.
Privacy and justification.Alexandra Couto - 2006 - Res Publica 12 (3):223-248.
Privacies: philosophical evaluations.Beate Rössler (ed.) - 2004 - Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press.
Privacy, Intimacy, and Isolation.Julie C. Inness - 1992 - New York, US: OUP Usa.
Is there a right to privacy?Steven Davis - 2009 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 90 (4):450-475.
The privacy of the psychical.Amihud Gilead - 2011 - Amsterdam: Rodopi.
Biobank research and the right to privacy.Lars Øystein Ursin - 2008 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 29 (4):267-285.
Four challenges for a theory of informational privacy.Luciano Floridi - 2006 - Ethics and Information Technology 8 (3):109–119.
Privacy, Separation, and Control.Steve Matthews - 2008 - The Monist 91 (1):130-150.

Analytics

Added to PP
2010-04-18

Downloads
182 (#104,539)

6 months
22 (#118,956)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Boudewijn de Bruin
University of Groningen

Citations of this work

Indiscriminate mass surveillance and the public sphere.Titus Stahl - 2016 - Ethics and Information Technology 18 (1):33-39.
Privacy in Public: A Democratic Defense.Titus Stahl - 2020 - Moral Philosophy and Politics 7 (1):73-96.
The Ethics of Cloud Computing.Boudewijn de Bruin & Luciano Floridi - 2017 - Science and Engineering Ethics 23 (1):21-39.
On Public‐identity Disempowerment.Laura Valentini - 2021 - Journal of Political Philosophy 30 (4):462-486.
Privacy and Punishment.Mark Tunick - 2013 - Social Theory and Practice 39 (4):643-668.

View all 11 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

How are power and unfreedom related.Ian Carter - 2008 - In Cécile Laborde & John W. Maynor (eds.), Republicanism and Political Theory. Blackwell. pp. 58--82.
Privacy: Its Meaning and Value.Adam D. Moore - 2003 - American Philosophical Quarterly 40 (3):215 - 227.
Imitation, media violence, and freedom of speech.Susan Hurley - 2004 - Philosophical Studies 117 (1-2):165-218.
Privacy, Autonomy, and Self-Concept.Joseph Kupfer - 1987 - American Philosophical Quarterly 24 (1):81 - 89.
Liberal and Republican Freedom.Boudewijn de Bruin - 2009 - Journal of Political Philosophy 17 (4):418-439.

View all 8 references / Add more references