“Seeing things”

Southern Journal of Philosophy 29 (S1):29-60 (1991)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

In an earlier discussion, I argued that Kant's moral theory satisfies some of the basic criteria for being a genuine theory: it includes testable hypotheses, nomological higher-and lower-level laws, theoretical constructs, internal principles, and bridge principles. I tried to show that Kant's moral theory is an ideal, descriptive deductive-nomological theory that explains the behavior of a fully rational being and generates testable hypotheses about the moral behavior of actual agents whom we initially assume to conform to its theoretical constructs. I argued that the moral "ought" is best understood as the "ought" of tentative prediction expressed in the range of uses of the German sollen; and that the degree to which such a theory is well-confirmed is a function of the degree to which we actually judge individual human agents, on a case-by-case basis, to be motivated by rationality, stupidity, or moral corruption in their actions. I assume that a similar case could be made for other major contenders, such as Utilitarianism or Aristotelianism. But there still remains unanswered the question of which of these theories is the best among the available alternatives. To answer this question, further criteria of selection must be invoked. Among these are structural elegance and explanatory simplicity, but even these do not exhaust the desiderata for an adequate moral theory. More pressing in the case of moral theory is the requirement that the theory enable us to understand all the available data of moral experience; that the theory be sufficiently inclusive that in the formulation of its descriptive laws and practical principles, it be capable of identifying as morally significant all the behavior to which moral praise, condemnation, or acquittal is a relevant and appropriate response.

Similar books and articles

Theories and things.W. V. O. Quine (ed.) - 1981 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
‘All Things Considered’.Ruth Chang - 2004 - Philosophical Perspectives 18 (1):1–22.
Thing and object.Kristie Miller - 2008 - Acta Analytica 23 (1):69-89.
Desire.Philip Pettit - 1998 - Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Causality and things in themselves.Kent Baldner - 1988 - Synthese 77 (3):353 - 373.
The Things Things Say.Jonathan Lamb - 2011 - Princeton University Press.
What Things Still Don’t Do. [REVIEW]David M. Kaplan - 2009 - Human Studies 32 (2):229 - 240.
Dreyfus and Spinosa on things-in-themselves.T. L. S. Sprigge - 1999 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 42 (1):115 – 124.

Analytics

Added to PP
2010-09-15

Downloads
246 (#79,090)

6 months
43 (#89,443)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Adrian M. S. Piper
APRA Foundation, Berlin

Citations of this work

Years of moral epistemology: A bibliography.Laura Donohue & Walter Sinnott-Armstrong - 1991 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 29 (S1):217-229.
20 Years of Moral Epistemology: A Bibliography.Walter Sinnott-Armstrong - 1991 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 29 (S1):217-229.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references