Classical logic without bivalence

Analysis 69 (2):211-218 (2009)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Semantic justifications of the classical rules of logical inference typically make use of a notion of bivalent truth, understood as a property guaranteed to attach to a sentence or its negation regardless of the prospects for speakers to determine it as so doing. For want of a convincing alternative account of classical logic, some philosophers suspicious of such recognition-transcending bivalence have seen no choice but to declare classical deduction unwarranted and settle for a weaker system; intuitionistic logic in particular, buttressed by assertion-conditional semantics, is often considered to enjoy a degree of meaning-theoretical respectability unattainable by classical logic.The decision to forgo the classical inference rules is not always made lightly. Thus, Dummett: " In the resolution of the conflict between [the view that generally accepted classical modes of inference ought to be theoretically accommodated, and the demand that any such accommodation be achieved without recourse to bivalence] lies, as I see it, one of the most fundamental and intractable problems in the theory of meaning; indeed, in all philosophy. "The present article ventures to suggest that the conflict need not be irresoluble. Helping ourselves only to such conceptual resources as are standardly invoked by proponents of intuitionistic logic, we shall formulate a rudimentary meaning theory for a selection of logical constants, define a relation of valid inferability, and prove that the latter includes all of classical first-order logic. The result is essentially that reported in Sandqvist as Theorem 2.20.2. TheoryWe will be considering a standard-syntax first-order language with ⊃, ⊥ and ∀ as its only primitive logical constants. We assume countable supplies of individual constants, individual functors , and predicates , as well as a denumerably infinite set of individual variables. By a basic 1 formula we will mean one that …[Full Text of this Article]

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,349

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Entailment and bivalence.Fred Seymour Michael - 2002 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 31 (4):289-300.
Excluded middle and bivalence.TimothyJ Day - 1992 - Erkenntnis 37 (1):93 - 97.
Pragmatism and bivalence.Cheryl Misak - 1990 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 4 (2):171 – 179.
Logic: an introduction.Greg Restall - 2006 - New York: Routledge.
Logic, quantum logic and empiricism.John Bell & Michael Hallett - 1982 - Philosophy of Science 49 (3):355-379.
On Partial and Paraconsistent Logics.Reinhard Muskens - 1999 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 40 (3):352-374.
Classical logic and truth-value gaps.Philip Hugly & Charles Sayward - 1992 - Philosophical Papers 21 (2):141-150.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-04-11

Downloads
149 (#122,736)

6 months
27 (#107,910)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Tor Sandqvist
Royal Institute of Technology, Stockholm

References found in this work

The logical basis of metaphysics.Michael Dummett - 1991 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Articulating reasons: an introduction to inferentialism.Robert Brandom - 2000 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Natural deduction: a proof-theoretical study.Dag Prawitz - 1965 - Mineola, N.Y.: Dover Publications.
Making it Explicit.Isaac Levi & Robert B. Brandom - 1996 - Journal of Philosophy 93 (3):145.
Anti-realism and logic: truth as eternal.Neil Tennant - 1987 - New York: Oxford University Press.

View all 24 references / Add more references