Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Falsificationism and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programs' in I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave.Imre Lakatos - 1970 - In Imre Lakatos & Alan Musgrave (eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Cambridge [Eng.]: Cambridge University Press.
  • Scientific reasoning: the Bayesian approach.Peter Urbach & Colin Howson - 1993 - Chicago: Open Court. Edited by Peter Urbach.
    Scientific reasoning is—and ought to be—conducted in accordance with the axioms of probability. This Bayesian view—so called because of the central role it accords to a theorem first proved by Thomas Bayes in the late eighteenth ...
  • The Scientific Image by Bas C. van Fraassen. [REVIEW]Michael Friedman - 1982 - Journal of Philosophy 79 (5):274-283.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   919 citations  
  • The curve fitting problem: A solution.Peter Turney - 1990 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 41 (4):509-530.
    Much of scientific inference involves fitting numerical data with a curve, or functional relation. The received view is that the fittest curve is the curve which best balances the conflicting demands of simplicity and accuracy, where simplicity is measured by the number ofparameters in the curve. The problem with this view is that there is no commonly accepted justification for desiring simplicity. This paper presents a measure of the stability of equations. It is argued that the fittest curve is the (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Curve Fitting Problem: A Solution1.Peter Turney - 1990 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 41 (4):509-530.
    Much of scientific inference involves fitting numerical data with a curve, or functional relation. The received view is that the fittest curve is the curve which best balances the conflicting demands of simplicity and accuracy, where simplicity is measured by the number ofparameters in the curve. The problem with this view is that there is no commonly accepted justification for desiring simplicity.This paper presents a measure of the stability of equations. It is argued that the fittest curve is the curve (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On Popper's definitions of verisimilitude.Pavel Tichý - 1974 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 25 (2):155-160.
    2 Popper's Logical Definition of Verisimilitude. 3 Popper's Probabilistic Definition of Verisimilitude. 4 Conclusion.
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   178 citations  
  • Reconstructing the Past. [REVIEW]Peter Godfrey-Smith - 1993 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (2):487-490.
  • Simplicity.Elliott Sober - 1975 - Oxford: Clarendon Press.
    Attempts to show that the simplicity of a hypothesis can be measured by attending to how well it answers certain kinds of questions.
  • Likelihood and convergence.Elliott Sober - 1988 - Philosophy of Science 55 (2):228-237.
    A common view among statisticians is that convergence (which statisticians call consistency) is a necessary property of an inference rule or estimator. In this paper, this view is challenged by appeal to an example in which a rule of inference has a likelihood rationale but is not convergent. The example helps clarify the significance of the likelihood concept in statistical inference.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Gruesome simplicity.Graham Priest - 1976 - Philosophy of Science 43 (3):432-437.
  • Logical versus historical theories of confirmation.Alan Musgrave - 1974 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 25 (1):1-23.
  • The accuracy of predictions.David Miller - 1975 - Synthese 30 (1-2):159 - 191.
    No categories
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • Popper’s qualitative theory of verisimilitude.David Miller - 1974 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 25 (2):166-177.
  • The Copernican Revolution: Planetary Astronomy in the Development of Western Thought.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1957 - Harvard University Press.
    The significance of the plurality of the Copernican Revolution is the main thrust of this undergraduate text In this study of the Copernican Revolution, the ...
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   214 citations  
  • The Copernican Revolution: Planetary Astronomy in the Development of Western Thought. Thomas S. Kuhn. [REVIEW]Philip P. Wiener - 1957 - Philosophy of Science 25 (4):297-299.
  • A Realistic Theory of Science.Clifford Alan Hooker - 1987 - State University of New York Press.
    This book presents a clear and critical view of the orthodox logical empiricist tradition, pointing the way to significant developments for the understanding of science both as research and as culture.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • A Realistic Theory of Science.Paul Thomson - 1990 - Noûs 24 (5):793-796.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Simplicity.David Hills - 1977 - Philosophical Review 86 (4):595.
  • Comments on David Miller.I. J. Good - 1975 - Synthese 30 (1-2):205 - 206.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Theory and Evidence.Clark N. Glymour - 1980 - Princeton University Press.
  • Foundations of Space-Time Theories.Michael Friedman - 1987 - Noûs 21 (4):595-601.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   242 citations  
  • Unification, explanation, and the composition of causes in Newtonian mechanics.Malcolm R. Forster - 1988 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 19 (1):55-101.
    William Whewell’s philosophy of scientific discovery is applied to the problem of understanding the nature of unification and explanation by the composition of causes in Newtonian mechanics. The essay attempts to demonstrate: the sense in which ”approximate’ laws successfully refer to real physical systems rather than to idealizations of them; why good theoretical constructs are not badly underdetermined by observation; and why, in particular, Newtonian forces are not conventional and how empiricist arguments against the existence of component causes, and against (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Problems of Old Evidence†.Ellery Eells - 2017 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 66 (3-4):283-302.
  • The Scientific Image.William Demopoulos & Bas C. van Fraassen - 1982 - Philosophical Review 91 (4):603.
  • A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science.Paul M. Churchland - 1989 - MIT Press.
    A Neurocomputationial Perspective illustrates the fertility of the concepts and data drawn from the study of the brain and of artificial networks that model the...
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   444 citations  
  • How the Laws of Physics Lie.Malcolm R. Forster - 1985 - Philosophy of Science 52 (3):478-480.
  • How the laws of physics lie.Nancy Cartwright - 1983 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    In this sequence of philosophical essays about natural science, the author argues that fundamental explanatory laws, the deepest and most admired successes of modern physics, do not in fact describe regularities that exist in nature. Cartwright draws from many real-life examples to propound a novel distinction: that theoretical entities, and the complex and localized laws that describe them, can be interpreted realistically, but the simple unifying laws of basic theory cannot.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1188 citations  
  • Saving the phenomena.James Bogen & James Woodward - 1988 - Philosophical Review 97 (3):303-352.
  • A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science.Lynne Rudder Baker & Paul M. Churchland - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (4):906.
  • The Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences: Volume 1: Founded Upon Their History.William Whewell - 2014 - Cambridge University Press.
    First published in 1840, this two-volume treatise by Cambridge polymath William Whewell remains significant in the philosophy of science. The work was intended as the 'moral' to his three-volume History of the Inductive Sciences, which is also reissued in this series. Building on philosophical foundations laid by Immanuel Kant and Francis Bacon, Whewell opens with the aphorism 'Man is the Interpreter of Nature, Science the right interpretation'. Volume 1 contains the majority of Whewell's section on 'ideas', in which he investigates (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Reconstructing The Past: Parsimony, Evolution, and Inference.Elliott Sober - 1988 - MIT Press.
    Reconstructing the Past seeks to clarify and help resolve the vexing methodological issues that arise when biologists try to answer such questions as whether human beings are more closely related to chimps than they are to gorillas. It explores the case for considering the philosophical idea of simplicity/parsimony as a useful principle for evaluating taxonomic theories of evolutionary relationships. For the past two decades, evolutionists have been vigorously debating the appropriate methods that should be used in systematics, the field that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   170 citations  
  • Foundations of Space-Time Theories.Micheal Friedman - 1983 - Princeton University Press.
  • Contrastive empiricism.Elliott Sober - 1990 - In C. Wade Savage (ed.), Scientific Theories. University of Minnesota Press. pp. 392--410.
    Realism and empiricism have always been contradictory tendencies in the philosophy of science. The view I will sketch is a synthesis, which I call Contrastive Empiricism. Realism and empiricism are incompatible, so a synthesis that merely conjoined them would be a contradiction. Rather, I propose to isolate important elements in each and show that they combine harmoniously. I will leave behind what I regard as confusions and excesses. The result, I hope, will be neither contradiction nor mishmash.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • A statistical paradox.D. V. Lindley - 1957 - Biometrika 44 (1/2):187-192.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • The Logic of Scientific Discovery.K. Popper - 1959 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 10 (37):55-57.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1313 citations  
  • Theory and Evidence.Clark Glymour - 1980 - Ethics 93 (3):613-615.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   192 citations  
  • The Logic of Scientific Discovery.Karl Popper - 1959 - Studia Logica 9:262-265.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1501 citations  
  • Conjectures and Refutations.K. Popper - 1963 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 21 (3):431-434.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1365 citations  
  • Unification and Scientific Realism Revisited.Malcolm R. Forster - 1986 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1986:394 - 405.
    Van Fraassen has argued that quantum mechanics does not conform to the pattern of common cause explanation used by Salmon as a precise formulation of Smart's 'cosmic coincidence' argument for scientific realism. This paper adds to this list some common examples from classical physics that also do not conform to Salmon's explanatory schema. This is bad news and good news for the realist. The bad news is that Salmon's argument for realism does not work; the good news is that realism (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Simplicity.Elliot Sober - 1976 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 166 (3):370-371.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations