Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. A theory of justice.John Rawls - unknown
    Though the revised edition of A Theory of Justice, published in 1999, is the definitive statement of Rawls's view, so much of the extensive literature on Rawls's theory refers to the first edition.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4022 citations  
  • What we owe to each other.Thomas Scanlon - 1998 - Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
    In this book, T. M. Scanlon offers new answers to these questions, as they apply to the central part of morality that concerns what we owe to each other.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2435 citations  
  • Moral dimensions: permissibility, meaning, blame.Thomas Scanlon - 2008 - Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
    The illusory appeal of double effect -- The significance of intent -- Means and ends -- Blame.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   572 citations  
  • A Theory of Justice: Revised Edition.John Rawls - 1999 - Harvard University Press.
    Previous edition, 1st, published in 1971.
  • The Realm of Rights by Judith Jarvis Thomson. [REVIEW]Carl Wellman - 1992 - Journal of Philosophy 89 (6):326-329.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   177 citations  
  • Promising, intimate relationships, and conventionalism.Seana Valentine Shiffrin - 2008 - Philosophical Review 117 (4):481-524.
    The power to promise is morally fundamental and does not, at its foundation, derive from moral principles that govern our use of conventions. Of course, many features of promising have conventional components—including which words, gestures, or conditions of silence create commitments. What is really at issue between conventionalists and nonconventionalists is whether the basic moral relation of promissory commitment derives from the moral principles that govern our use of social conventions. Other nonconventionalist accounts make problematic concessions to the conventionalist's core (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  • Relationships and Responsibilities.Samuel Scheffler - 1997 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 26 (3):189-209.
  • Having reasons.Mark Schroeder - 2008 - Philosophical Studies 139 (1):57 - 71.
    What is it to have a reason? According to one common idea, the "Factoring Account", you have a reason to do A when there is a reason for you to do A which you have--which is somehow in your possession or grasp. In this paper, I argue that this common idea is false. But though my arguments are based on the practical case, the implications of this are likely to be greatest in epistemology: for the pitfalls we fall into when (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   135 citations  
  • Two concepts of rules.John Rawls - 1955 - Philosophical Review 64 (1):3-32.
  • Rationalism about Obligation.David Owens - 2008 - European Journal of Philosophy 16 (3):403-431.
    In our thinking about what to do, we consider reasons which count for or against various courses of action. That having a glass of wine with dinner would be pleasant and make me sociable recommends the wine. That it will disturb my sleep and inhibit this evening’s work counts against it. I determine what I ought to do by weighing these considerations and deciding what would be best all things considered. A practical reason makes sense of a course of action (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Which relationships justify partiality? The case of parents and children.Niko Kolodny - 2010 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 38 (1):37-75.
  • A Treatise of Human Nature.David Hume & A. D. Lindsay - 1958 - Philosophical Quarterly 8 (33):379-380.
  • The Wrong Kind of Reason.Pamela Hieronymi - 2005 - Journal of Philosophy 102 (9):437 - 457.
    A good number of people currently thinking and writing about reasons identify a reason as a consideration that counts in favor of an action or attitude.1 I will argue that using this as our fundamental account of what a reason is generates a fairly deep and recalcitrant ambiguity; this account fails to distinguish between two quite different sets of considerations that count in favor of certain attitudes, only one of which are the “proper” or “appropriate” kind of reason for them. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   291 citations  
  • Professional ethics: The separatist thesis.Alan Gewirth - 1986 - Ethics 96 (2):282-300.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Causeless complicity.Christopher Kutz - 2007 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 1 (3):289-305.
    I argue, contrary to standard claims, that accomplice liability need not be a causal relation. One can be an accomplice to another’s crime without causally contributing to the criminal act of the principal. This is because the acts of aid and encouragement that constitute the basis for accomplice liability typically occur in contexts of under- and over-determination, where causal analysis is confounded. While causation is relevant to justifying accomplice liability in general, only potential causation is necessary in particular cases. I (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • The Ethics of Advocacy.Robert Audi - 1995 - Legal Theory 1 (3):251-281.
    Nearly everyone is at times an advocate. By professional role, some people act quite regularly as advocates: lawyers, legislators, executives, merchants, and, in many contexts, educators. Lawyers often consider themselves obligated to maintain a special “zeal” toward their clients' interests, and there are many laws and principles of legal ethics that govern advocacy by attorneys. This article concerns the ethics of advocacy, not its legal aspects. Indeed, I cannot even address the full range of moral issues raised by advocacy; I (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reasonable Partiality in Professional Relationships.Brenda Almond - 2005 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 8 (1-2):155-168.
    First, two aspects of the partiality issue are identified: (1) Is it right/reasonable for professionals to favour their clients interests over either those of other individuals or those of society in general? (2) Are special non-universalisable obligations attached to certain professional roles?Second, some comments are made on the notions of partiality and reasonableness. On partiality, the assumption that only two positions are possible – a detached universalism or a partialist egoism – is challenged and it is suggested that partiality, e.g. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Promises, reasons, and normative powers.Gary Watson - 2009 - In David Sobel & Steven Wall (eds.), Reasons for Action. Cambridge University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Specifying norms as a way to resolve concrete ethical problems.Henry S. Richardson - 1990 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 19 (4):279-310.
  • A Simple Theory of Promising.David Owens - 2006 - Philosophical Review 115 (1):51-77.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality.R. M. Dworkin - 2002 - Philosophical Quarterly 52 (208):377-389.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   494 citations  
  • Giving Practical Reasons.David Enoch - 2011 - Philosophers' Imprint 11.
    I am writing a mediocre paper on a topic you are not particularly interested in. You don't have, it seems safe to assume, a (normative) reason to read my draft. I then ask whether you would be willing to have a look and tell me what you think. Suddenly you do have a (normative) reason to read my draft. By my asking, I managed to give you the reason to read the draft. What does such reason-giving consist in? And how (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • 5. Razian Authority and Its Implications for Legal Ethics.WBradley Wendel - 2010 - Legal Ethics 13 (2):191.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Practical Reasons and Moral ".Patricia Greenspan - 2007 - In Russ Shafer-Landau (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics: Volume Ii. Clarendon Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Value and the Right Kind of Reason.Mark Schroeder - 2010 - In Russ Shafer-Landau (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics, Volume 5. Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Lawyers and Justice.David Luban - 1990 - Law and Philosophy 9 (3):311-317.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The Morality of Freedom.Joseph Raz - 1986 - Philosophy 63 (243):119-122.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   991 citations  
  • Role Morality as a Complex Instance of Ordinary Morality.Judith Andre - 1991 - American Philosophical Quarterly 28 (1):73 - 80.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations