Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. A right to do wrong.Jeremy Waldron - 1981 - Ethics 92 (1):21-39.
  • I_– _T. M. Scanlon.T. M. Scanlon - 2000 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74 (1):301-317.
  • Intention and permissibility, I.T. M. Scanlon - 2000 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74 (1):301–317.
    [T. M. Scanlon] It is clearly impermissible to kill one person because his organs can be used to save five others who are in need of transplants. It has seemed to many that the explanation for this lies in the fact that in such cases we would be intending the death of the person whom we killed, or failed to save. What makes these actions impermissible, however, is not the agent's intention but rather the fact that the benefit envisaged does (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Intention and Permissibility, I.Thomas Scanlon - 2000 - Supplement to the Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 74 (1):301-317.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Intention and Permissibility.T. M. Scanlon & Jonathan Dancy - 2000 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74:301-338.
    [T. M. Scanlon] It is clearly impermissible to kill one person because his organs can be used to save five others who are in need of transplants. It has seemed to many that the explanation for this lies in the fact that in such cases we would be intending the death of the person whom we killed, or failed to save. What makes these actions impermissible, however, is not the agent's intention but rather the fact that the benefit envisaged does (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Intention and Permissibility.T. M. Scanlon & Jonathan Dancy - 2000 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74:301-338.
    It is clearly impermissible to kill one person because his organs can be used to save five others who are in need of transplants. It has seemed to many that the explanation for this lies in the fact that in such cases we would be intending the death of the person whom we killed, or failed to save. What makes these actions impermissible, however, is not the agent's intention but rather the fact that the benefit envisaged does not justify an (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • On Punishment.A. M. Quinton - 1953 - Analysis 14 (6):133 - 142.
  • Self-defense and the problem of the innocent attacker.Jeff McMahan - 1994 - Ethics 104 (2):252-290.
    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • The metaphysics of harm.Matthew Hanser - 2008 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77 (2):421-450.
  • The Metaphysics of Harm.Matthew Hanser - 2008 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77 (2):421-450.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • The justification of deterrent violence.Daniel M. Farrell - 1990 - Ethics 100 (2):301-317.
  • A Right to Violate One's Duty.Enoch David - 2002 - Law and Philosophy 21 (4-5):355-384.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The right to threaten and the right to punish.Warren Quinn - 1985 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 14 (4):327-373.