Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The Paradox of Self-Consciousness.[author unknown] - 2000 - Philosophical Quarterly 50 (199):277-280.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • The Paradox of Self-Consciousness.[author unknown] - 2000 - Mind 109 (433):135-138.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Mind and World.John McDowell - 1994 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Much as we would like to conceive empirical thought as rationally grounded in experience, pitfalls await anyone who tries to articulate this position, and ...
  • Bezieht sich nach Kant die Anschauung unmittelbar auf Gegenstände?Peter Rohs - 2001 - In Ralph Schumacher, Rolf-Peter Horstmann & Volker Gerhardt (eds.), Kant Und Die Berliner Aufklärung: Akten des Ix. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. Bd. I: Hauptvorträge. Bd. Ii: Sektionen I-V. Bd. Iii: Sektionen Vi-X: Bd. Iv: Sektionen Xi-Xiv. Bd. V: Sektionen Xv-Xviii. New York: De Gruyter. pp. 214-228.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Kant's metaphysic of experience.H. J. Paton - 1936 - London,: G. Allen & Unwin.
  • Science and metaphysics: variations on Kantian themes.Wilfrid Sellars - 1968 - New York,: Humanities P..
  • Kant and the foundations of analytic philosophy.Robert Hanna - 2001 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Robert Hanna presents a fresh view of the Kantian and analytic traditions that have dominated continental European and Anglo-American philosophy over the last two centuries, and of the connections between them. But this is not just a study in the history of philosophy, for out of this emerges Hanna's original approach to two much-contested theories that remain at the heart of contemporary philosophy. Hanna puts forward a new 'cognitive-semantic' interpretation of transcendental idealism, and a vigorous defense of Kant's theory of (...)
  • Spielen nach Kant die Kategorien schon bei der Wahrnehmung eine Rolle? Peter Rohs und John McDowell (Do the Categories According to Kant Play a Role Already in Perception? Peter Rohs and John McDowell).Christian Helmut Wenzel - 2005 - Kant Studien 96 (4):407-426.
    Ob die Kategorien schon bei der Wahrnehmung eine Rolle spielen, wird von Kant-Interpreten unterschiedlich gesehen. Peter Rohs etwa argumentiert für eine Unabhängigkeit und Selbständigkeit der Wahrnehmung gegenüber dem Verstand. Die intuitive Synthesis der Einbildungskraft müsse auf eigenen Füßen stehen können und Bilder und „singuläre Sinne“ der Anwendung der Begriffe vorausgehen. McDowell hingegen spricht sich gegen eine solche Selbständigkeit der Wahrnehmung aus. Setzte man sie voraus, käme der Verstand immer zu spät . Die Argumente beider Seiten sollen am Text Kants untersucht (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • The Paradox of Self-Consciousness. [REVIEW]Adam Morton - 2001 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63 (3):727-730.
    I discuss Bermudez' minimalist approach to self-consciousness approvingly, connecting it with other positions in philosophy and trying to separate it from ideas about non-conceptual content.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  • Making Sense of Kant’s Schematism.Michael Pendlebury - 1995 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (4):777-797.
    In this paper I advance an account of Kant’s Schematism according to which a schema in general is a pattern of imaginative synthesis that explains how intuitions have the content required for them to fall under a concept corresponding to the schema. An empirical schema is a pattern of imaginative synthesis that is responsive to the qualities of the sensations involved in the intuition which it synthesizes. A transcendental schema, in contrast, is not responsive to the particular qualities of the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Mind and World.John McDowell - 1994 - Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 58 (2):389-394.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   814 citations  
  • Kant and nonconceptual content.Robert Hanna - 2005 - European Journal of Philosophy 13 (2):247-290.
  • Kant and Nonconceptual Content.Robert Hanna - 2005 - European Journal of Philosophy 13 (2):247-290.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   113 citations  
  • Lawfulness without a Law.Hannah Ginsborg - 1997 - Philosophical Topics 25 (1):37-81.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Empirical concepts and the content of experience.Hannah Ginsborg - 2006 - European Journal of Philosophy 14 (3):349-372.
    The view that the content of experience is conceptual is often felt to conflict with the empiricist intuition that experience precedes thought, rather than vice versa. This concern is explicitly articulated by Ayers as an objection both to McDowell and Davidson, and to the conceptualist view more generally. The paper aims to defuse the objection in its general form by presenting a version of conceptualism which is compatible with empiricism. It proposes an account of observational concepts on which possession of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Understanding and sensibility.Stephen Engstrom - 2006 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 49 (1):2 – 25.
    Kant holds that the human cognitive power is divided into two "stems", understanding and sensibility. This doctrine has seemed objectionably dualistic to many critics, who see these stems as distinct parts, each able on its own to produce representations, which must somehow interact, determining or constraining one another, in order to secure the fit, requisite for cognition, between concept and intuition. This reading cannot be squared, however, with what Kant actually says about theoretical cognition and the way understanding and sensibility (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Sensibility and Understanding.S. Engstrorn - 2006 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 49 (1):2-25.
  • The Paradox of Self-Consciousness: Representation and Mind.José Luis Bermúdez - 1998 - MIT Press.
  • Mind and World.John Mcdowell - 1996 - Philosophical Quarterly 46 (182):99-109.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   978 citations  
  • The role of imagination in Kant's theory of experience.Wilfrid Sellars - 1978 - In Henry W. Johnstone Jr (ed.), Categories: A Colloquium. Pennsylvania State University. pp. 231-245.
  • Kant's Metaphysic of Experience.H. J. Paton - 1937 - Philosophy 12 (45):99-104.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  • Thinking the particular as contained under the universal.Hannah Ginsborg - 2006 - In Rebecca Kukla (ed.), Aesthetics and Cognition in Kant's Critical Philosophy. Cambridge University Press.
    In a well-known passage from the Introduction to Kant’s Critique of Judgment, Kant defines the power or faculty of judgment [Urteilskraft] as "the capacity to think the particular as contained under the universal" (Introduction IV, 5:179).1 He then distinguishes two ways in which this faculty can be exercised, namely as determining or as reflecting. These two ways are defined as follows: "If the universal (the rule, the principle, the law) is given, then judgment, which subsumes the particular under it... is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Imagination and perception.P. F. Strawson - 1982 - In Ralph Charles Sutherland Walker (ed.), Kant on Pure Reason. Oxford University Press.