Switch to: Citations

References in:

Reliabilism and induction

Synthese 97 (3):297 - 334 (1993)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. What is Justified Belief?Alvin I. Goldman - 1979 - In George Pappas (ed.), Justification and Knowledge: New Studies in Epistemology. Boston: D. Reidel. pp. 1-25.
    The aim of this paper is to sketch a theory of justified belief. What I have in mind is an explanatory theory, one that explains in a general way why certain beliefs are counted as justified and others as unjustified. Unlike some traditional approaches, I do not try to prescribe standards for justification that differ from, or improve upon, our ordinary standards. I merely try to explicate the ordinary standards, which are, I believe, quite different from those of many classical, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   895 citations  
  • The foundations of scientific inference.Wesley C. Salmon - 1967 - [Pittsburgh]: University of Pittsburgh Press.
    Not since Ernest Nagel’s 1939 monograph on the theory of probability has there been a comprehensive elementary survey of the philosophical problems of probablity and induction. This is an authoritative and up-to-date treatment of the subject, and yet it is relatively brief and nontechnical. Hume’s skeptical arguments regarding the justification of induction are taken as a point of departure, and a variety of traditional and contemporary ways of dealing with this problem are considered. The author then sets forth his own (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   194 citations  
  • Scientific reasoning: the Bayesian approach.Peter Urbach & Colin Howson - 1993 - Chicago: Open Court. Edited by Peter Urbach.
    Scientific reasoning is—and ought to be—conducted in accordance with the axioms of probability. This Bayesian view—so called because of the central role it accords to a theorem first proved by Thomas Bayes in the late eighteenth ...
  • Word and Object.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1960 - Cambridge, MA, USA: MIT Press.
    In the course of the discussion, Professor Quine pinpoints the difficulties involved in translation, brings to light the anomalies and conflicts implicit in our ...
  • Relativism Refuted: A Critique of Contemporary Epistemological Relativism.Harvey Siegel - 1987 - Springer Verlag.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • Level-Confusions in Epistemology.William P. Alston - 1980 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 5 (1):135-150.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  • IV.—Inference from the Known to the Unknown.John Watling - 1955 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 55 (1):83-108.
  • Cartesian Skepticism and Inference to the Best Explanation.Jonathan Vogel - 1990 - Journal of Philosophy 87 (11):658-666.
  • A defense of skepticism.Peter Unger - 1971 - Philosophical Review 80 (2):198-219.
  • Probability and Hume's inductive scepticism.David Charles Stove - 1973 - Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.
    This book aims to discuss probability and David Hume's inductive scepticism. For the sceptical view which he took of inductive inference, Hume only ever gave one argument. That argument is the sole subject-matter of this book. The book is divided into three parts. Part one presents some remarks on probability. Part two identifies Hume's argument for inductive scepticism. Finally, the third part evaluates Hume's argument for inductive scepticism. Hume's argument that induction must be either deductively valid or circular because based (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Reason and Scepticism.Michael A. Slote - 1970 - Philosophy 46 (178):363-365.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Relativism, truth, and incoherence.Harvey Siegel - 1986 - Synthese 68 (2):225-259.
    There are many contemporary sources and defenders of epistemological relativism which have not been considered thus far. I have, for example, barely touched on the voluminous literature regarding frameworks, conceptual schemes, and Wittgensteinian forms of life. Davidson's challenge to the scheme/content distinction and thereby to conceptual relativism, Rorty's acceptance of the Davidsonian argument and his use of it to defend a relativistic position, Winchian and other sociological and anthropological arguments for relativism, recent work in the sociology of science, and Goodman's (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Relativism refuted.Harvey Siegel - 1982 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 14 (2):47–50.
  • Justification, discovery and the naturalizing of epistemology.Harvey Siegel - 1980 - Philosophy of Science 47 (2):297-321.
    Reichenbach's well-known distinction between the context of discovery and the context of justification has recently come under attack from several quarters. In this paper I attempt to reconsider the distinction and evaluate various recent criticisms of it. These criticisms fall into two main groups: those which directly challenge Reichenbach's distinction; and those which (I argue) indirectly but no less seriously challenge that distinction by rejecting the related distinction between psychology and epistemology, and defending the "naturalizing" of epistemology. I argue that (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Goodmanian Relativism.Harvey Siegel - 1984 - The Monist 67 (3):359-375.
    Nelson Goodman’s work is universally regarded as pioneering and fundamental, and his attempts to clarify the nature of induction, symbol systems, art, theorizing and understanding have received and continue to receive great attention. Central to that work is a view Goodman describes as “radically relativist.” Goodman’s unusual brand of relativism, however, while basic to the entire Goodman corpus, has yet to be carefully delineated and studied. I hope in this paper to begin such a study. I will first briefly review (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Brown on epistemology and the new philosophy of science.Harvey Siegel - 1983 - Synthese 56 (1):61 - 89.
    For over two decades, something akin to a scientific revolution in philosophy of science has been taking place. So, at any rate, claims Harold I. Brown, in his book Perception, Theory and Commitment: The New Philosophy of Science, in which he chronicles and defends the demise of logical empiricism and offers a new philosophy of science in its stead. The new philosophy of science, drawing on the work of Kuhn, Toulmin, Hanson, Lakatos, Polanyi, and others, but effectively structured, enhanced, and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Foundationalism, coherentism, and the levels gambit.David Shatz - 1983 - Synthese 55 (1):97 - 118.
    A central problem in epistemology concerns the justification of beliefs about epistemic principles, i.e., principles stating which kinds of beliefs are justified and which not. It is generally regarded as circular to justify such beliefs empirically. However, some recent defenders of foundationalism have argued that, within a foundationalist framework, one can justify beliefs about epistemic principles empirically without incurring the charge of vicious circularity. The key to this position is a sharp distinction between first- and second-level justifiedness.In this paper I (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Circularity and epistemic principles: A reply to James Keller.David Shatz - 1986 - Synthese 68 (2):369-382.
    This paper is a reply to James Keller 's criticisms of my Foundationalism, Coherentism and the Levels Gambit.Foundationalists have often claimed that, within a foundationalist framework, one can justify beliefs about epistemic principles in a mediate, empirical fashion, while escaping the charge of vicious circularity that is usually thought to afflict such methods of justification. In my original paper I attacked this foundationalist strategy; I argued that once mediate, empirical justification of epistemic principles is allowed, the foundationalist must also allow (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Does the philosophy of induction rest on a mistake?R. D. Rosenkrantz - 1982 - Journal of Philosophy 79 (2):78-97.
  • Inference, Method and Decision.David Miller - 1980 - Philosophical Quarterly 30 (120):264.
  • Phenomenal properties.Michael E. Levin - 1981 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 42 (March):42-58.
  • Metaphysics and the Mind-Body Problem.Michael E. Levin - 1979 - New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Kripke's argument against the identity thesis.Michael E. Levin - 1975 - Journal of Philosophy 72 (March):149-67.
  • Knowledge.Keith Lehrer - 1974 - Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Mathematical Knowledge. [REVIEW]W. D. Hart - 1977 - Journal of Philosophy 74 (2):118-129.
  • Epistemology and cognition.Alvin I. Goldman - 1986 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    Against the traditional view, Alvin Goldman argues that logic, probability theory, and linguistic analysis cannot by themselves delineate principles of rationality or justified belief. The mind's operations must be taken into account.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   823 citations  
  • Discrimination and perceptual knowledge.Alvin I. Goldman - 1976 - Journal of Philosophy 73 (November):771-791.
    This paper presents a partial analysis of perceptual knowledge, an analysis that will, I hope, lay a foundation for a general theory of knowing. Like an earlier theory I proposed, the envisaged theory would seek to explicate the concept of knowledge by reference to the causal processes that produce (or sustain) belief. Unlike the earlier theory, however, it would abandon the requirement that a knower's belief that p be causally connected with the fact, or state of affairs, that p.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   747 citations  
  • A causal theory of knowing.Alvin I. Goldman - 1967 - Journal of Philosophy 64 (12):357-372.
    Since Edmund L. Gettier reminded us recently of a certain important inadequacy of the traditional analysis of "S knows that p," several attempts have been made to correct that analysis. In this paper I shall offer still another analysis (or a sketch of an analysis) of "S knows that p," one which will avert Gettier's problem. My concern will be with knowledge of empirical propositions only, since I think that the traditional analysis is adequate for knowledge of nonempirical truths.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   373 citations  
  • Conclusive reasons.Fred I. Dretske - 1971 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 49 (1):1-22.
  • Healthy Scepticism.James Franklin - 1991 - Philosophy 66 (257):305 - 324.
    The classical arguments for scepticism about the external world are defended, especially the symmetry argument: that there is no reason to prefer the realist hypothesis to, say, the deceitful demon hypothesis. This argument is defended against the various standard objections, such as that the demon hypothesis is only a bare possibility, does not lead to pragmatic success, lacks coherence or simplicity, is ad hoc or parasitic, makes impossible demands for certainty, or contravenes some basic standards for a conceptual or linguistic (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Knowledge and the flow of information.F. Dretske - 1989 - Trans/Form/Ação 12:133-139.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1374 citations  
  • Knowledge and the Flow of Information.Fred I. Dretske - 1981 - Stanford, CA: MIT Press.
    This book presents an attempt to develop a theory of knowledge and a philosophy of mind using ideas derived from the mathematical theory of communication developed by Claude Shannon. Information is seen as an objective commodity defined by the dependency relations between distinct events. Knowledge is then analyzed as information caused belief. Perception is the delivery of information in analog form for conceptual utilization by cognitive mechanisms. The final chapters attempt to develop a theory of meaning by viewing meaning as (...)
  • Hume's skeptical solution and the causal theory of knowledge.Francis W. Dauer - 1980 - Philosophical Review 89 (3):357-378.
  • Reliability, Justification, and the Problem of Induction.James van Cleve - 1984 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 9 (1):555-567.
  • Hypothesis confirmation is induction by enumeration.F. M. Christensen - 1998 - Philosophia 26 (1-2):79-103.
  • Mathematical truth.Paul Benacerraf - 1973 - Journal of Philosophy 70 (19):661-679.
  • The Significance of Naturalized Epistemology.Barry Stroud - 1981 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 6 (1):455-472.
  • Reason and Scepticism.Michael Slote - 1970 - New York: Routledge.
    First published in 2002. Routledge is an imprint of Taylor & Francis, an informa company.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The anatomy of inquiry.Israel Scheffler - 1963 - Indianapolis,: Bobbs-Merrill.
  • Blindspots.Roy A. Sorensen - 1988 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Sorensen here offers a unified solution to a large family of philosophical puzzles and paradoxes through a study of "blindspots": consistent propositions that cannot be rationally accepted by certain individuals even though they might by true.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   252 citations  
  • Belief, Truth and Knowledge.D. M. Armstrong - 1973 - London,: Cambridge University Press.
    A wide-ranging study of the central concepts in epistemology - belief, truth and knowledge. Professor Armstrong offers a dispositional account of general beliefs and of knowledge of general propositions. Belief about particular matters of fact are described as structures in the mind of the believer which represent or 'map' reality, while general beliefs are dispositions to extend the 'map' or introduce casual relations between portions of the map according to general rules. 'Knowledge' denotes the reliability of such beliefs as representations (...)
  • Discrimination and Perceptual Knowledge.Alvin I. Goldman - 2000 - In Sven Bernecker & Fred I. Dretske (eds.), Knowledge: Readings in Contemporary Epistemology. Oxford University Press. pp. 86-102.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   405 citations  
  • The warrant of induction.D. H. Mellor - 1991 - In Matters of Metaphysics. Cambridge University Press.
  • Epistemology.Alvin Goldman - 2003 - In John Shand (ed.), Fundamentals of Philosophy. Routledge. pp. 11-35.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • A Causal Theory of Knowing.Alvin I. Goldman - 2000 - In Sven Bernecker & Fred I. Dretske (eds.), Knowledge: Readings in Contemporary Epistemology. Oxford University Press. pp. 18-30.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   204 citations  
  • Alvin I. Goldman, Epistemology and Cognition[REVIEW]Darryl Bruce - 1989 - Synthese 79 (1):165-169.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   383 citations  
  • Goldman's psychologism: Review of Epistemology and Cognition[REVIEW]Paul Thagard - 1986 - Erkenntnis 34 (1):117-123.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   343 citations  
  • .Richard Alston - 2015
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Probability and Hume's Inductive Scepticism.D. C. Stove - 1973 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 35 (3):646-647.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Probability and Hume's Inductive Scepticism.D. C. Stove - 1976 - Mind 85 (338):297-298.