Switch to: Citations

References in:

Who Is Afraid of Numbers?

Utilitas 20 (4):447 (2008)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. A theory of justice.John Rawls - unknown
    Though the revised edition of A Theory of Justice, published in 1999, is the definitive statement of Rawls's view, so much of the extensive literature on Rawls's theory refers to the first edition.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4022 citations  
  • Mortal Questions.[author unknown] - 1979 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 43 (3):578-578.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   519 citations  
  • Equality.Thomas Nagel - 1979 - In Mortal questions. New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Let them Eat Chances: Probability and Distributive Justice.David Wasserman - 1996 - Economics and Philosophy 12 (1):29-49.
    Jon Elster reports that in 1940, and again in 1970, the U.S. draft lottery was challenged for falling short of the legally mandated ‘random selection’. On both occasions, the physical mixing of the lots appeared to be incomplete, since the birth dates were clustered in a way that would have been extremely unlikely if the lots were fully mixed. There appears to have been no suspicion on either occasion that the deficiency in the mixing was intended, known, or believed to (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Can a Nonconsequentialist Count Lives?David Wasserman & Alan Strudler - 2003 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 31 (1):71-94.
  • The individualist lottery: How people count, but not their numbers.Jens Timmermann - 2004 - Analysis 64 (2):106–112.
  • The individualist lottery: how people count, but not their numbers.J. Timmermann - 2004 - Analysis 64 (2):106-112.
  • Inequality.Andrew Moore - 1995 - Philosophical Quarterly 45 (178):114-115.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Inequality.Jan Narveson - 1996 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (2):482-486.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Replies.T. M. Scanlon - 2002 - Social Theory and Practice 28 (2):337-358.
  • Replies.T. M. Scanlon - 2003 - Ratio 16 (4):424–439.
  • Replies.Thomas Scanlon - 2002 - Ratio 16 (4):424-439.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Reasons and Persons.Joseph Margolis - 1986 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 47 (2):311-327.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1638 citations  
  • Justifiability to each person.Derek Parfit - 2003 - Ratio 16 (4):368–390.
    sonable, in this sense, if we ignore, or give too little weight to, some other people's well-being or moral claims.' Some critics have suggested that, because Scanlon appeals to this sense of 'reasonable', his formula is empty. On this objection, whenever we believe that some act is wrong, we shall believe that people have moral claims not to be treated in this way. We could therefore argue that such acts are disallowed by some principle which no one could reasonably reject, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  • Scanlon and the claims of the many versus the one.Michael Otsuka - 2000 - Analysis 60 (3):288-293.
    In "What We Owe to Each Other", T. M. Scanlon argues that one should save the greater number when faced with the choice between saving one life and two or more different lives. It is, Scanlon claims, a virtue of this argument that it does not appeal to the claims of groups of individuals but only to the claims of individuals. I demonstrate that this argument for saving the greater number, indeed, depends, contrary to what Scanlon says, upon an appeal (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • How to be consistent without saving the greater number.Kirsten Meyer - 2006 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 34 (2):136–146.
  • Fairness in life and Death Cases.Gerald Lang - 2005 - Erkenntnis 62 (3):321-351.
    John Taurek famously argued that, in ‘conflict cases’, where we are confronted with a smaller and a larger group of individuals, and can choose which group to save from harm, we should toss a coin, rather than saving the larger group. This is primarily because coin-tossing is fairer: it ensures that each individual, regardless of the group to which he or she belongs, has an equal chance of being saved. This article provides a new response to Taurek’s argument. It proposes (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Contractualism on saving the many.R. Kumar - 2001 - Analysis 61 (2):165-170.
  • Precis of Morality, Mortality, Vol. 1: Death and Whom to Save from ItMorality, Mortality, Vol. 1: Death and Whom to Save from It. [REVIEW]Frances Kamm - 1998 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (4):939.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Owing, justifying, and rejecting. [REVIEW]F. M. Kamm - 2002 - Mind 111 (442):323-354.
  • Morality, Mortality, Vol. 1: Death and Whom to Save from It.Frances Kamm - 1998 - Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 58 (4):963-967.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Aggregation and two moral methods.F. M. Kamm - 2005 - Utilitas 17 (1):1-23.
    I begin by reconsidering the arguments of John Taurek and Elizabeth Anscombe on whether the number of people we can help counts morally. I then consider arguments that numbers should count given by F. M. Kamm and Thomas Scanlon, and criticism of them by Michael Otsuka. I examine how different conceptions of the moral method known as pairwise comparison are at work in these different arguments and what the ideas of balancing and tie-breaking signify for decision-making in various types of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Weighted lotteries in life and death cases.Iwao Hirose - 2007 - Ratio 20 (1):45–56.
    Faced with a choice between saving one stranger and saving a group of strangers, some people endorse weighted lotteries, which give a strictly greater chance of being saved to the group of strangers than the single stranger. In this paper I attempt to criticize this view. I first consider a particular version of the weighted lotteries, Frances Kamm's procedure of proportional chances, and point out two implausible implications of her proposal. Then, I consider weighted lotteries in general, and claim (1) (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Saving the greater number without combining claims.Iwao Hirose - 2001 - Analysis 61 (4):341–342.
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Saving the greater number without combining claims.I. Hirose - 2001 - Analysis 61 (4):341-342.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Aggregation and numbers.Iwao Hirose - 2004 - Utilitas 16 (1):62-79.
    This article considers the reach of arguments for saving the greater number without interpersonal aggregation, and argues that interpersonal aggregation is useful to encompass the proper respect due to each separate person. I first give a precise definition of interpersonal aggregation, which many non-utilitarians try to avoid. Then, I show that consequentialism and Scanlon can justify the case for the greater number without interpersonal aggregation. However, I propose the Aggregation Approach, which justifies the case for the greater number in some (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Aggregation and Numbers.Iawo Hirose - 2004 - Utilitas 16 (1):62-79.
    This article considers the reach of arguments for saving the greater number without interpersonal aggregation, and argues that interpersonal aggregation is useful to encompass the proper respect due to each separate person. I first give a precise definition of interpersonal aggregation, which many non-utilitarians try to avoid. Then, I show that consequentialism and Scanlon can justify the case for the greater number without interpersonal aggregation. However, I propose the Aggregation Approach, which justifies the case for the greater number in some (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Selecting people randomly.John Broome - 1984 - Ethics 95 (1):38-55.
  • Weighing Goods: Equality, Uncertainty and Time.John Broome - 1991 - Wiley-Blackwell.
    This study uses techniques from economics to illuminate fundamental questions in ethics, particularly in the foundations of utilitarianism. Topics considered include the nature of teleological ethics, the foundations of decision theory, the value of equality and the moral significance of a person's continuing identity through time.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   452 citations  
  • Should the numbers count?John Taurek - 1977 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 6 (4):293-316.
  • Saving the Greatest Number.Thom Brooks - 2002 - Logique Et Analyse 45 (177-178):55-59.
    Imagine there are three boats equidistant from one another. You are alone in the first boat. The other two boats are sinking fast: one boat has one person (A), the other has two persons (B&C). There is only enough time to allow saving either A or B&C before their boats sink, drowning whoever is onboard. Will we always combine claims of those wishing to be saved and rescue B&C? Otsuka says that the 'Kamm-Scanlon' contractualist framework that does not aggregating various (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Morality of Freedom.Joseph Raz - 1986 - Philosophy 63 (243):119-122.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   991 citations